I. C. Golaknath & Ors Vs.
State of Punjab & ANR [1967] INSC 45 (27 February 1967)
27/02/1967 RAO, K. SUBBA (CJ) RAO, K. SUBBA
(CJ) WANCHOO, K.N.
HIDAYATULLAH, M.
SHAH, J.C.
SIKRI, S.M.
BACHAWAT, R.S.
RAMASWAMI, V.
SHELAT, J.M.
BHARGAVA, VISHISHTHA MITTER, G.K.
VAIDYIALINGAM, C.A.
CITATION: 1967 AIR 1643 1967 SCR (2) 762
CITATOR INFO :
RF 1967 SC1776 (7) F 1968 SC1395 (7) RF 1970
SC 898 (61) RF 1972 SC 425 (7,16,21) D 1972 SC 963 (27) O 1973 SC1461
(10,15,16,17,25,30,32,37,50,51 RF 1975 SC2299 (251,325,522,576,577,649) F 1976
SC 490 (196) RF 1976 SC1207 (283,285,397,548) R 1977 SC1027 (42) R 1978 SC 68
(89,101,233,261) D 1978 SC 489 (9) E&R 1978 SC 597 (19) RF 1979 SC1550 (9)
RF 1980 SC1762 (5) RF 1980 SC1789 (86) RF 1981 SC 271 (33,42) RF 1981 SC 431
(10) R 1984 SC 326 (8) O 1984 SC 684 (65) RF 1987 SC1140 (3) R 1987 SC1986 (29)
F 1991 SC 101 (131) RF 1991 SC1676 (66,71)
ACT:
Constitution of India, Arts. 13(2), 368, 245,
248, Schedule 7, List 1. Entry 97-Power to amend Constitution where resides-Whether
resides in Art. 368 or in residuary power of Parliament under Art. 248 read
with Entry 97 List 1Fundamental Rights in Part III whether can be amended and
abridged by the procedure in Art. 368-Law' under Art. 13(2) Whether Includes
constitutional amendments-Scheme of Constitution Fundamental rights whether
intended to be permanent and un-amendable-Amendment whether exercise of
sovereign power-Amendment whether a political matter outside the purview of
courts.
Constitution Seventeenth Amendment Act,,
1964-Whether invalid for contravention of Art. 13(2).
Prospective overruling, doctrine of-Vast
agrarian changes under constitutional amendments-Necessity of preserving past
while protecting future decisis.
Punjab Security of Land Tenures Act, 1953
(Act 10 of 1953)Mysore Land Reforms Act (Act 10 of 1962) as amended by Act 14
of 1965-Acts contravening fundamental rights-Whether valid.
HEADNOTE:
The validity of the Punjab Security of Land
Tenures Act, 1953 (Act 10 of 1953) and of the Mysore Land Reforms Act (Act 10
of 1962) as amended by Act 14 of 1965 was challenged by the petitioners under
Art. 32 of the Constitution. Since these Acts were included in the 9th Schedule
to the Constitution by the Constitution (Seventeenth) Amendment Act, 1964, the
validity of the said Amendment Act was also challenged. In this connection it
was urged that Sankari Prasad's case in which the validity of the constitution
(First) Amendment Act, 1951 had been upheld and Sajjan Singh's case in which
the validity of the Constitution (Seventeenth) Amendment Act, 1964, had been
upheld by this Court, had been wrongly decided. It was contended that
Parliament had no power to amend fundamental rights in Part III of the
Constitution.
HELD: Per Subba Rao, C.J., Shah, Sikri,
Shelat and Vaidialingam, JJ. (Hidayatullah, J. Concurring) :
Fundamental Rights cannot be abridged or
taken away by the amending procedure in Ail. 368 of the Constitution. An
amendment to the Constitution is 'law' within the meaning of Art. 13(2) and is
therefore subject to Part III of the Constitution. Sri Sankari Prasad Singh Deo
v. Union of India
Rajasthan, [1965] 1 S.C.R. 933, reversed. Per
Subba, Rao, C.J., Shah, Sikri, Shelat and Vaidialingam, JJ.
(i) Fundamental rights are the primordial
rights necessary for the development of human personality. They are the rights
which enable a 763 man to chalk out his own life in the manner he likes best.
Our Constitution, in addition to the
well-known fundamental rights, also included the rights of minorities and other
backward communities in such rights. [789 E] The fundamental rights are given a
transcendental position under our Constitution and are kept beyond the reach of
Parliament. At the same time Parts III and IV of the Constitution constituted
an integrated scheme forming a self contained code. The scheme is made so
elastic that all the Directive Principles of State Policy can reasonably be
enforced without taking away or-abridging the fundamental rights. While
recognisingthe immutability of the fundamental rights, subject to social
control the Constitution itself provides for the suspension or the modification
of fundamental rights under specific circumstances, as in Arts. 33, 34 and 35.
The non-obstante clause with which the last article opens makes it clear that
all the other provisions of the Constitution are subject to this provision.
Article 32 makes the right to move the Supreme Court by appropriate proceedings
for the enforcement of the rights conferred by the said Parts a fundamental
right. Even during grave emergencies Art. 358 only suspends Art. 19 and all
other rights are untouched except those specifically suspended by the President
under Art. 359. [789 H; 790 D] The Constitution has given a place of permanence
to the fundamental freedoms. In giving to themselves the Constitution the
people have reserved the fundamental freedoms to themselves. Art. 13 merely in-corporate
that reservation. The Article is however not the source of the protection of
fundamental rights but the expression of the reservation. The importance
attached to the fundamental freedoms is so transcendatal that a bill enacted by
a unanimous vote of all the members of both Houses is ineffective to derogate
from its guaranteed exercise. It is not what Parliament regards at a given
moment as conducive to the public benefit but what Part III declarer.
protected, which determines the ambit of the freedom. The incapacity of
Parliament therefore in exercise of its amending power to modify, restrict, or
impose fundamental freedoms in Part III arises from the scheme of the Constitution
and the nature of the freedoms. [792 D-F] A. K. Gopalan v. State of Madras,
[1950] S.C.R.88, State of Madras v. Smt. Champakam Dorairajan, (1951) S.C.R.
525, Pandit M. S. M. Sharma v. Shri Sri
Krishna Sinha, [1959] Supp. 1 S.C.R. 806 and Ujjam Bai v. State of Uttar
Pradesh, [1963] 1 S.C.R. 778, referred to.
If it is the duty of Parliament to enforce
directive principles it is equally its duty to enforce them without infringing
the fundamental rights. The verdict of Parliament on the scope of the law of
social control of fundamental rights is not final but justiciable. If it were
not so, the whole scheme of the Constitution would break.
[815 H; 816 A-B] , (ii)Article 368 in terms
only prescribes various steps in the matter of amendment. The article assumes
the power to amend found elsewhere. The completion of the procedural steps
cannot be said to culminate in the power to amend for if that was so the
Constitution makers could have stated that in the Constitution. Nor can the
power be implied either from Art. 368 or from the nature of the articles sought
to be amended; the doctrine of necessary implication cannot be invoked if there
is an express provision. There is no necessity to imply any such power as
Parliament has the plenary power to make any law including the law to amend the
Constitution subject to the limitations laid down therein [793 E-G] (iii)The
power of Parliament to amend the Constitution is derived from Arts. 245, 246
and 248 read with item 97 in List I. The residuary 764 power of Parliament can
certainly take in the power to amend the Constitution. [794 A-D] Though a law
made under Art. 245 is subject to the provisions of the Constitution it would
be wrong to say that every law of amendment made under it would necessarily be
inconsistent with the articles sought to be amended. It cannot reasonably be
said that a law amending an article is inconsistent with it. The limitation in
Art. 245 is in respect of the power to make a law and not of the content of the
law made within the scope of its power. [794 E-F] An order by the President
under Art. 392 cannot attract Art 368 as the amendment contemplated by the
latter provisions can be initiated only by the introduction of a bill in
Parliament. It cannot therefore be said that if the power of amendment is held
to be a legislative power the President acting under Art. 392 can amend the
Constitution in terms of Art. 368. [794 G-H] (iv) The Constituent Assembly, it
so minded, could certainly have conferred an express legislative power on
Parliament to amend the Constitution by ordinary legislative process.
There is, therefore, no inherent
inconsistency between legislative process and the amending one. Whether in the
field of a constitutional law or statutory law amendment can be brought about
only by 'law'. [794 C-D] Article 13(2), for the purpose of that Article, gives
an inclusive definition of 'law'. It does not Prima facie exclude
constitutional law. The process under Art. 368 itself closely resemble the
legislative process.
Article 368 is not a complete code in respect
of the procedure of amendment. The details of procedure in respect of other
bills have to be followed so far as possible in respect of a Bill under Art.
368 also, The rules made by the House of the People providing procedure for
amendments lay down a procedure similar to that of other bills with the
addition of certain special provisions. If amendment is intended to be
Something other than law the constitutional insistence on the said legislative
process is unnecessary.
The imposition of further conditions is only
a safeguard against the hasty action or a protection to the states but does not
change the legislative character of the amendment [795 G 796 C] Article 3 of
the Constitution permits changes in States and their boundaries by a
legislative process under Arts. 4 and 169 amendments in the Solution are made
by 'law' but by a fiction are deemed not to be amendments for the purpose of
Art. 368. This shows that amendment is law and that but for the fiction it
would be an amendment within the meaning of Art, 368. [796 C-F] Therefore
amendments either under Art. 368 or under other Articles are only made by
Parliament following the legislative process and are 'law' for the purpose of
Art.
13(2). [798 C] Mccawley v. The king,
[1920]A.C., 691 and The Bribery Commissioner v. Pedrick Ransinghe, [1964] 2
W.L.R. 1301, referred to.
(v) One need not cavil at the description of
amending power as a sovereign power for it is sovereign only within the scope
of the power conferred by a particular Constitution which may expressly limit
the power of amendment both substantive and procedural. If cannot therefore be
said that amending power can have no limitations being a sovere4p power. [804]
The argument that the amending process involves political questions and is
therefore outside the scope of judicial review cannot also be accepted It may
be Parliament seeks to amend the Constitution for political reasons but the
court in denying that power will not be deciding 765 a political question; it
will only be holding that Parliament has no power to armed Particular articles
of the Constitution for any purpose whatsoever, be it political or otherwise.
[804 E-G] (vi) If power to abridge the fundamental rights is denied to
Parliament revolution is not a necessary result. The existence of an all
comprehensive power cannot prevent revolution if there is chaos in the country
brought about by misrule or abuse of power. Such considerations are out of
place in construing the provisions of the Constitution by a Court of law. [816
B-C] (vii) While-ordinarily @ Court will be reluctant to reverse its previous
decisions it is its duty in the constitutional field to correct itself as early
as possible, for otherwise the future progress of the country and happiness of
the people will be at stake. As it was clear that the decision in Sankari
Prasad's case was wrong, it was pre-eminently a typical case where this Court
should overrule it. The longer it held the field the greater the scope for
erosion of fundamental rights. As it contained the seeds of destruction of the
cherished rights of the people, the sooner it was overruled the better for the
country. [816 G-H] The Superintendent and Legal Remembrancer Stale of West
Bengal v. The Corporation at Calcutta, [1967] 2 S.C.R., 170 relied on.
(viii) The Constitution (Seventeenth
Amendment) Act, 1964, inasmuch as it takes away or abridges fundamental rights
was beyond 'the amending power of Parliament and void because of contravention
of Art. 13(2). But having regard to the history of this and earlier amendment
to the Constitution, their effect on the social and economic affairs of the
country and the chaotic situation that may be brought about by the sudden with drawl
at this stage of the amendments from the Constitution it was undesirable to
give retroactivity of this decision. The present was therefore a fit case for
the application of the doctrine of "prospective. overruling, evolved by
the courts in the United States of America. [805 E; 807 E, G; 808 C-D] Great
Northern Railway v. Sunburst Oil & Ref. Co. (1932) 287 U.S. 358: 77 L. Ed.
360, Chicot County Drainage v.
Baxter State Bank, (1940) 308 U.S. 371,
Griffin v. Illionis, (1956) 351 U.S. 12, Wolf v. Colorado, 338 U.S. 25 : 193 L.
Ed. 872, Mapp v. Ohio, 367 U.S. 643 : 6 L.
Ed. (2nd Edn.) 1081 and Link letter v. Walker, (1965) 381 U.S. 618, referred
to.
(ix), The doctrine of "prospective
overruling" is a modern doctrine suitable for a fast moving society. It
does not do away with the doctrine of state decision but confines it to past
transactions. While in Strict theory it may be said that the doctrine 'involves
the making of law, *hat the court really does is to declare the law but refuse
to give retroactivity to it. It is really a pragmatic solution reconciling the
two conflicting doctrines, namely, that a court finds the law and that it does
make law It finds law but restricts its operation to the future. It enables the
court to bring about a smooth transition by correcting, its errors without
disturbing the impact of those errors on past transactions. By the application
of this doctrine the past may be preserved and the future protected. [913 A-C;
814 EF] Our Constitution does not expressly of by necessary implication speak
against the doctrine of prospective overruling. Articles 32, 141 and 142 are
designedly made comprehensive to enable the Supreme Court to declare law and to
give such directions or pass such orders as are necessary to do complete
justice. The expression 'declared' in Art.
141 is wider than the words 'found or made'.
The law declared by the Supreme Court is the law of the land.. If so, there is
no acceptable reason why 7 66 the Court, in declaring the law in supersession
of the law declared by it earlier, could not restrict the operation of the law
as declared to the future and save the transactions whether statutory or
otherwise that were affected on the basis of the earlier law. [813 F-H] As this
Court for the first time has been called upon to apply the doctrine evolved in
a different country under different circumstances, it would like to move warily
in the beginning and would lay down the following propositions :
(1) The doctrine of prospective overruling
can be invoked only in matters arising under our Constitution; (2) it can be
applied only by highest court of the country is. the Supreme Court as it has
the constitutional jurisdiction to declare law binding on all the Courts as it
has India; (3) the scope of the retrospective operation of the law declared by
the supreme Court superseding its earlier decisions is left to its discretion
to be moulded in accordance withthe justice of the cause or matter before it.
[814 C-D] Applying the doctrine of prospective overruling in the circumstances
of the present case the Court declared that this decision would not affect the
validity of the Constitution (Seventeenth Amendment) Act 1964, or other
amendments to the Constitution taking away or abridge the fundamental rights.
It further declared that in future Parliament will have no power to amend Part
III of Abe Constitution so as to take away or abridge the fundamental rights.
[814 F-G] (x) As according to the above decision the Constitution (Seventeenth
Amendment) Act held the field the validity of the two impugned Acts, namely the
Punjab Security of Land Tennures Act, 10 of 1953 and the Mysore Land Reforms
Act, 10 of 1962, as amended by Act 14 of 1965, could, not be questioned on the
ground that they offended Art 13, 14 or 31 of the Constitution. [815 E] (xi) On
the findings the following, questions did not fall to be considered :
(a) Whether in the exercise of the power of
amendment the fundamental structure of the Constitution may be changed or even
destroyed or whether the power is restricted to making modification within the
framework of the original instrument for its better effectuation ? (b) Whether
the amendment of fundamental rights is covered by the proviso to Art. 368 ? (c)
To what extent can the provisions of die Constitution other than fundamental
rights be amended ? (d) To what extent can Part III be amended otherwise thin
by taking away or abridging the fundamental rights ? (e) Whether the impugned
Act could be sustained under the provisions of the Constitution without the aid
of Arts. 31A and 31B of the Schedule.
Obiter If necessity to abridge the
fundamental rights does arise the residuary power of Parliament may be relied
upon to call for a constituent by for making a new Constitution or radically
changing it. The recent Act providing for a poll in Goa, Daman and Diu was an
instance of analogus exercise of such residuary power by the Parliament, [816
E-F] Per Hidayatullah. J. : (i) The scope of the amending power under the Constitution
is not to be determined by taking an apriori view of the 767 omni competence of
Art. 368. When there is conflict between that Article and Art. 13(2) juridical
hermeneutics requires the Court to interpret them by combining 'them and not by
destroying one with the aid of the other. No part in a Constitution is superior
to another part unless the Constitution-itself says so and there is no
accession of strength to any provision. by calling it a code. It is, the
context of the legal provisions that illustrates the meaning of the different
parts so that among them and between them there should be correspondence and
harmony. [857 H-858C] (ii) It is wrong to think of the Fundamental Rights as
within Parliament's giving or taking. They are secured to the people by Arts.
12, 13, 32, 136, 141,,144 and 226. The High Courts and finally this Court have
been made the Judges of whether any lagislative or executive action on the part
of the State, considered as comprehensively as is possible,offends the
Fundamental Rights and Art.
13(2)declares that legislation which so
offends is to be deemed to be void. The general words of art. 368 cannot be
taken to mean that by calling an Act an Amendment of the Constitution Act a
majority of total strengths and a 2/3rds majority of the members present and
voting in each House may remove not only any of the Fundamental Rights but the
whole Chapter giving them. [860 A-D; 867 FF] (iii) In Britain there is no
distinction between constitutional law and' ordinary law as to the procedure of
their enactment. In our Constitution too in spite of the claim that Art. 368 is
a Code Arts. 4, 11 and 169 show that the amendment of the Constitution can be
by the ordinary law making procedure. By this method one of the legislative
limbs in a State can be removed or created. This destroys at one stroke the
claim that Art. 368 is a code and. also that any special method of amendment of
the Constitution is fundamentally necessary. [861 E-G] The only difference
between constitutional law and ordinary law can, be said to arise from the fact
that constitutional laws are generally amend-able under a process which in
varying degrees, is more difficult or elaborate. This may give a distinct
character to the law of the Constitution but it does not serve to distinguish
it from the other laws of the land for the purpose of Art. 13(2). The Article
itself does not exclude constitutional law which could have been easily done
had the constitution makers. so intended. [862 B; 866 B] An amendment to the
Constitution is not made under power derived' from Arts. 245 or 248 of the
Constitution read with entry 97 of List 1. The power of amendment is sui
generis.
[900 E] (iv) A narrow view need not be taken
of the word amendment'.. By an amendment new matter may be added, old matter
removed or altered. The power of amending the Constitution is however not
intended to be used for experiments or as an escape, from restrictions against
undue State action enacted in the Constitution itself. Nor is the power of
amendment available for the purpose of removing express or implied restrictions
against the State. [862 F; 863 B-C] Coleman v. Milter, 307 U.S. 443 (83 L. Ed.
1385), Luther V. Borden,, 7 How. 1(12 L. Ed. 58) and Baker v. Carr, 369 U.S.
186 (7 L. Ed. 2d., 633), referred to.
The State is no doubt supreme but in the
supremacy of its powers it may create impediments on its own sovereignty.
There is nothing to prevent the State from
placing certain matters outside the amending procedure. When this happens the
ordinary procedure of amendment ceases to apply.
Amendment can then only be by a freshly
constituted body..
768 To attempt to do this otherwise is to
attempt revolution which is to alter the will of the people in an illegal
manner. Courts can interfere to nullify the revolutionary change because there
is an infraction of exiting legality.
Democracy may be lost if there is no liberty
based on law and law based on equality. The protection of the fundamental
rights is necessary so that we may not walk in fear of democracy itself. [863
G; 864 A-C; 865 A-D] (v) In Art. 13(2) the restriction is against the State.
There is a difference between the State and
its agencies such as Government, Parliament, the Legislature of the States, and
the local and other authorities. The State means more than any of these or all
of them put together.
By making the State subject to Fundamental
Rights it is clearly stated in Art. 13(2) that any of the agencies acting alone
or all the agencies acting together are not above the Fundamental Rights.
Therefore when theHouse of the People or the Council of States introduces a Bill
for the abridgement of the Fundamental Rights, it ignores the injunction
against it and even if the two Houses pass the Bill the injunction is next
operative against the President since the expression Government of India in the
General Clauses Act means the President of India. Thus the injunction in Art.
13(2) is against the whole force of the State acting either in its executive or
legislative capacity. [866 E-H] (vi) It is wrong to invoke the Directive
Principles as if there is some antinomy between them and the Fundamental
Rights. The Directive Principles lay down the routes of State action but such
action must avoid the restrictions stated in the Fundamental Rights. It cannot
be conceived that in following the Directive Principles the Fundamental Rights
can be ignored. [867 G, 868 B] (vii) Our Constitution has given a guaranteed
right to the persons whose fundamental rights are affected to move the Court.
The guarantee is worthless if the rights are capable of being taken away. This
makes our Constitution unique and the American or other foreign precedents
cannot be of much assistance. [875 H] Hollingsworth v. Virginia, 3 Dall. 378,
Leser v. Garnett, 258 U.S. 130, Dillon v. Gloss, 256 U.S. 368 and Texas v. White,
7 Wall, 700, referred to.
It is not that Fundamental Rights are not
subject to any change or modification. The Constitution permits a curtailment
of the exercise of most of the Fundamental Rights by stating the limits of that
curtailment. It permits the Fundamental Rights to be controlled but prohibits
their erasure. [878 B] (viii) Parliament today is not the constituent body as
the constituent 'assembly was but a constituted body which must bear true
allegiance to the Constitution as by law established. To change the Fundamental
Part of the individuals liberty is a usurpation of the constituent functions
because they have been placed outside the scope of the power of the constituted
Parliament. [870 B-D] Our Constitution like some others has kept certain
matters outside the amendatory process so that the their representatives. In
Art. 35 obstante clause. They exclude Article under the proviso. It is
therefore a great error to think of Art. 368 as a code or as omni competent.
[901 C-E;
902 A-B] 769 Garnishee case, 46 C.L.R. 155,
referred to.
Article 368 cannot directly be amended by
Parliament to confer power on itself over the fundamental rights, It would be
against Art. 13(2). Parliament cannot do indirectly what it cannot do directly.
[878 H] (ix) If it is desired to abridge the Fundamental Rights the legal
method is that the State must reproduce the power which it has chosen to put
under restraint. Parliament must amend Art. 368 to convoke another constituent
assembly, pass a law under item 97 of the List 1 of Schedule 7 to call a
constituent assembly, and then that assembly may be able to abridge or take
away the fundamental rights. Any other method must be regarded as
revolutionary. [878 D-E; 879 B] (x) The various amendments that have been made
by Parliament in Arts. 15, 16 and 19 did not abridge fundamental rights and
were therefore valid. [879 C, 883 B] (xi) Our Constitution accepted the theory
that Right of Property is a fundamental right though perhaps it was an error to
do so if socialisation was desired. It treated property rights as inviolable
except through law for public good and on payment of compensation. However the
various amendments have significantly changed the position. As a result of
them, except for land within the prescribed ceiling, all other land can be
acquired or rights therein extinguished or modified without compensation and no
challenge to the law can be made under Arts. 14, 19 or 31 of the Constitution.
[887 B; 888 B-C; 896 F-G] As there is apprehension that the erosion of the
right to property may be practised against other fundamental rights it is
necessary to call a halt. An attempt to abridge or take away Fundamental Rights
by a constituted Parliament even through an amendment of the Constitution can I
declared void. This Court has the power and the jurisdiction to do so. The
opposite view expressed in Sajjan Singh's case was wrong.. [898 B-C] (xii) The
First, Fourth and Seventh amendments of the Constitution, cannot now be
challenged because of long acquiescence. It is good sense and sound policy for
the courts to decline to take up an amendment for consideration after a
considerable lapse of time when it was not challenged before or was sustained
on an earlier occasion after challenge. [893 O, H 1902 D-E] Lesser v. Garnett,
258 U.S. 130 (1922), referred to.
(xiii) In the Seventeenth Amendment, the
extension of the definition of 'estate' to include ryotwari and agricultural
lands is an inroad into the Fundamental Rights but it cannot be questioned in
view, of the existence of Art. 3 1A(1) (a) whose validity cannot now be
challenged. The new definition of estate introduced by the amendment is beyond
the reach of the Courts not because it is not law but because it is
"law" and fills within that word in Art. 31(1) (2) (2A) and Art. 3
1-A(1). [899 C-G] The third section of the Act is however invalid. It adds 44
State Acts to the ninth schedule. The Schedule is being used to give advance
protection to-legislation which is known or apprehended to derogate,from the
Fundamental Rights. The power under Art. 368 was not meant to give protection
to State statute-, which offend the Constitution.
The intent here is to silence the courts and
not to amend the Constitution. [900 A-D] 770 (xiv) The two impugned Acts namely
the Punjab Security of Land Tenures Act, 1953 and the Mysore Land Reforms Act,
1962 as amended are valid under the Constitution not because they are included
in Schedule 9 of the Constitution but because they are protected by Art. 3 1-A
and the President's assent. [902 G-H] Per Wanchoo, Bachawat, Ramaswami, Bhargava
and Mitter, JJ.
(dissenting): Article 368 carries the power
to amend all parts of the Constitution including the fundamental rights in Part
III of the Constitution. An amendment is not 'law' for the purpose of Art.
13(2) and cannot be tested under that Article.
Sri Sankari Prasad Singh Deo v. Union of
India, [1952] S.C.R. 89 and Sajjan Singh v. State of Rajasthan, [1965] 1 S.C.R.
933, reaffirmed.
Per Wanchoo, Bhargava and Mitter, JJ.-(i) The
Constitution provides a separate part headed 'Amendment of the Constitution'
and Art. 368 is the only article in that Part.
There can therefore, be no doubt that the
power to amend the Constitution must be contained in Art. 368. If there was any
doubt in the matter it is resolved by the words, namely, "the Constitution
shall stand amended in accordance with the terms of the bill". These words
can only mean that the power is there to amend ,the Constitution after the
procedure has been followed. [826 A-D] (ii) While there is a whole part devoted
to the amendment of the Constitution there is no specific mention of the
amendment of the Constitution in Art. 248 or in any entry of List 1. It would
in the circumstances 'be more appropriate to read the power in Art. 368 than in
Art. 248 read with item 97 of List I. [826 H-827 A] The original intention of
the Constitution makers was to give residuary power to the States. The mere
fact that during the passage of the Constitution by the Constituent Assembly
residuary power was finally vested in the Union would not therefore mean that
it includes the power to amend the Constitution. Moreover residuary power
cannot be used to change the fundamental law of the Constitution because all
legislation is under Art. 245 "subject to the provisions of this
Constitution". [827 B, H] Mere accident of similarity of procedure
provided in Art.
368 to that provided for ordinary legislation
cannot obliterate the basic difference 'between constitutional law and ordinary
law. It is the quality and nature of what is done under Art. 368 and not its similarity
to other procedure that should be stressed. What emerges after the procedure in
Art. 368 has been followed is not ordinary law but fundamental law. [829 D; 830
C-D] (iii) The procedure under the proviso to Art. III cannot apply to a 'bill
to amend the Constitution. If the President refused to, give his assent to such
a bill-, the proposed amendment falls. In this respect at any rate the
procedure under Art. 368 differs from, the ordinary legislative process. [831
B-E] (iv) The word 'law' has been avoided apparently with great care in
Art.368. What emerges after the procedure has been followed is not an Act but
the Constitution stands amended.
After that the courts can only see whether
the procedure in Art. 368 was followed. If it has been followed there is no
question of testing the amendment of the Constitution On the avail of
fundamental rights or in any other way as in the case of ordinary legislation.
[832 A-G] 771 (v) To say that 'amendment' in law only means a change which
results in improvement would make amendment impossible for what is improvement
is a matter of opinion. [834 B] It may be open to doubt whether the power of
amendment contained in Art. 368 goes to the extent of completely abrogating the
present Constitution and substituting I it by an entirely new one. But short of
that the power to amend includes the power to add any provision to the
Constitution to alter any provision and substitute any other provision in its
place or to delete any provision. [834 F-G] The seventeenth amendment is merely
in exercise of the power of amendment as indicated above and cannot be struck
down on the ground that it goes beyond the power conferred by Parliament to
amend the Constitution by Art. 368. [834 H] (vi) There is no express limitation
on power of amendment in Art. 368 and no limitation can or should be implied
therein.
If the Constitution makers intended certain
basic provisions in the Constitution, and Part III in particular, to be not
amendable there is no reason why it was not so stated in Art. 3 68. The
acceptance of the principle that them is an implied bar to amendment of basic
features of the Constitution would lead to the position that any amendment to
any article would be liable to challenge before the courts on the ground that
it amounted to amendment of a basic feature. Constituent power like that in Art
368 can only be subject to express limitations so far as the substance of the
amendments is concerned. [835 A; 836 D, G] (vii) For interpreting Art. 369 it
is not permissible to read the speeches made in the Constituent Assembly.
Historical facts namely what was accepted or
what was not accepted or what was avoided in the Constituent Assembly can be
looked into; but in connection with Art. 368 no help can be got from the
historical material available. [838 C] Administrator General, of Bengal v. Prem
Lal Mullick, (1895) XXII I.A107, Baxter v. Commissioner of Taxation, (1907) 4
C.I.R. 1087, A. K. Gopalan v. State of Madras [1950] S.C.R.
88 and The Automobile Transport (Rajasthan)
Ltd. v. State of Rajasthan, [1963] 1 S.C.R. 491, referred to.
(viii) The preamble to the Constitution
cannot prohibit or control in any way or impose any implied restrictions or
limitations on the power to amend the Constitution contained in Aft. 368. [838
H] In re the Berubari Union and Exchange of Enclaves, [1960] 3 S.C.R. 250,
referred to.
(ix) The word 'law' in Art. 13(1) does not
include. any law in the nature of a constitutional.provision for no such law
remained in view of Art. 395 which provided that "the Indian Independence
Act, 1947 and the Government of India Act, 1935, together with all enactments
amending or supplementing the latter Act, but not including the Abolition of
Privy Council Jurisdiction Act, 1949, are hereby repealed. There is no reason
why if the word 'law' in Art. 13(1) relating to past laws does not include any
constitutional provision theword 'law' in cl. (2) would take in an amount of
the Constitution for it would be reasonable to read the word in the same sense
in both the clauses. [839 D-F] Article 13 (2) when it talks of the State making
any law, refers to the law made under the provisions contained in Ch.
1 of Part XI of the Constitution beginning
with Art. 245.
It can have no reference to the 772
Constituent power of amendment under Art. 368. For it is somewhat contradictory
that in Art. 368 power should have been given to amend any provision of the
Constitution without any limitations but indirectly that power should be
limited by using words of doubtful import in Art. 13(25.[841 C] The power
conferred by the words of Art. 368 being unfettered, inconsistency between.
that power and the provision in Art. 13(2) must be avoided. Therefore in
keeping with the unfettered power in Art. 368 the word 'law' in Art. 13(2) must
be read as meaning law passed under the ordinary legislative power and not a
constitutional amendment. The words in Art. 13(2) are not specific and clear
enough to be regarded as an express limitation on Art.
368. [842 G-H] (x) Merely because there was
some indirect effect on Art.
226 it was not necessary that the Seventeenth
Amendment should have been ratified under the proviso to Art. 368.
Art. 245 had not also been directly affected
by the said Act and no ratification %-as required on this ground either.
[843 G-H; 846 C] (xi) The laws added to the
Ninth Schedule by the Seventeenth Amendment Act had already been passed by the
State Legislatures and it was their constitutional infirmity, if any, which was
being cured by the device adopted in Art. 31B read with the Ninth Schedule, the
amendment being only of the relevant provisions of Part III which were
compendiously put in one place in Art. 31B. Parliament could alone do it under
Art. 368 and there was no necessity for any ratification under the proviso, for
amendment of Part HI is not entrenched in the proviso. [847 E] In curing the
infirmity of the said laws Parliament was not encroaching on the exclusive
legislative powers of the States because only Partiament could card the
infirmity.
For the same reason the fact that the laws in
question were State laws did. not make ratification obligatory.. [847 G] A
limited meaning cannot be given to Art, 368 because of the possibility of abuse
of the power. The check is not in the courts but in the people who plect members
of Parliament.
[848 F] The power of amendment contained in a
written federal constitution is a safety valve which to a large extent provides
for stable growth and makes violent revolution more or less unnecessary. The
fact that in the last sixteen years a large number of amendments , could be
made and have been made is due to the accident that one party has been returned
by electors in sufficient strength to be able to command Special majorities
which are required in Art. 368, not only at the Centre but in all the States.
But that is no ground for limiting the clear words of Art. 368. [850 CD, E]
(xii)Though the period for which Sankari Prasad's case has stood unchallenged
is not long, the effects which have followed on the passing of State laws on the
faith of that decision, are so overwhelming that the decision should not be
disturbed otherwise chaos will follow. This is the fittest possible case in
which the principle of stare decisis should be applied [851 G] Keshav Mills:
Company, Ltd V Commissioner of Incometax,[1965] 2 S.C.R. 908, referred to.
(xii)The doctrine of prospective overruling
cannot be accepted in this country. The doctrine accepted here is that courts
declare law and that a declaration made by a court is the law of the land and
takes effect 773 from the date the law came into force. It would be undesirable
to give up that doctrine and supersede it with the doctrine of prospective
overruling. [852,D-F] Moreover a law contravening Art. 13(2) is void ab initio
as held by this Court in Deep Chand's case and Mahendra Lal Jaini's case. In
the face of these decisions it is impowible to apply the doctrine of
prospective overruling to ordinary laws. If constitutional law is to be treated
as ordinary law the same principle applies. If however it is not treated as
'law' under Art. 13(2) then there is no necessity of applying the principle of
prospective overruling for in that case the amendment under Art. 368 does not
have to be tested under Art. 13(2). [852 G-H; 853 B] Deep Chand v. St ate of Uttar
Pradesh, [1959] Supp. 2 S.C.R.
8 and Mahendra, Lal Jaini v. State of Uttar
Pradesh, [1963] Supp. 1 S.C.R. 912, referred to.
Per Bachawat J.-(i) Article 368 not only
prescribes the procedure but also gives the power of amendment. It is because
the power to amend is given by the article that by following its procedure the
Constitution stands amended.
The proviso is enacted on the assumption that
the several articles mentioned in it are amendable; but for the proviso they
would have been amendable under the main part. There is no other provision in
the Constitution under which these articles' can be amended. [904 D] Articles
4, 169, Fifth Schedule Part D and Sixth Schedule Para 21 empower the Parliament
to make amendments to certain parts of the Constitution by law, and by, express
provision such law is deemed not to be amendment for the purpose of Art. 368.
All other provisions of the Constitution can be amended by recourse to Art. 368
only. No other article confers the power of amending the Constitution. [904E-F]
(ii) The power to amend the Constitution cannot be said to reside in Art. 248
and List 1, item 97 because if amendment could be made by ordinary legislative
process Art. 368 would be meaningless. Under the residual power the Parliament
has no competence to make any law with respect to any matter enumerated in
Lists II and III of the 7th Schedule, but under Art. 368 even Lists 11 and III
can be amended.
Moreover a law passed by residual power is
passed by virtue of Art. 245 and must be subject to the provisions of the
Constitution so that it cannot derogate from the Constitution or amend it. Such
a law would be void. [905 CP] (iii) Article 368 gives the power of amending
'this Constitution'. This Constitution means every part of the Constitution
including Part ITT and Art. 13(2). Thus Art.
13(2) is also within the reach of the
amending power.
Instead of controlling Art. 368 it is
controlled by that Article. [906 C-D; H] (iv) The contention that a
constitutional amendment under Art. 368 is a law within the meaning of Art. 13
must be rejected. The distinction between the Constitution and law is so
fundamental that the Constitution is not regarded as a law or a legislative
act. The Constitution mean-, the Constitution as amended. An amendment made in
conformity with Art. 368 is a part of the Constitution and is likewise not law.
Save as expressly provided in Arts. 4, 169 Fifth Schedule Part D and Sixth
Schedule para 21 no law can amend the Constitution and a law which purports to
make such an amendment is void. It is for this reason that Art. 368 avoids all
reference to law making by the Parliament. There 3 Sup. CI./67-4 774 are. also
material differences between the ordinary law making procedure and the
procedure under the Article. [907 B-F; 908 D-H] If a constitutional amendment
creating a new fundamental rights and incorporating it in Part III were a law,
it would not be open to the Parliament by a subsequent amendment to abrogate
the new fundamental right for such an amendment would be repugnant to Part 111.
But the conclusion is absurd for the body which enacted the right can surely
take it away by the same process. [909 E] Marbury v. Madison, (1803) 1 Cranch
137 :2 L.Ed. 60 and Riley v. Carter, 88 A.L.R. 1008, referred to.
(v) There is no conflict between Arts. 13(2)
and 368. The two articles operate in different fields, the former in the field
of law, the latter in that of constitutional amendment. [910 B] (vi) The
non-obstante clause in Art. 35 does not show that the article is not amendable.
The non-obstante clause is to be found also in, Arts. 258(1). 364, 369, 370 and
371A. No one has suggested that these articles are not amendable.
[910 D] (vii) The words 'fundamental' used in
regard to rights in Part III and the word guaranteed in Art. 32 do not mean
that the said rights cannot be amended. The constitution is never at rest; it
changes with the progress of time. The scale of values in Parts III and IV is
not immortal and these Parts being parts of the Constitution are not immune
from amendment under Art. 368. [910 F-G] The impugned amendments to be
Constitution were made to meet the situations created by decisions of this
Court and to carry out urgent agrarian reforms. If it is held that the rights,
conferred by Part III cannot be abridged or taken away by constitutional
amendments, all these amendments would be invalid. The Constitution makers
could not have intended that the ' rights conferred by Part III could not be
altered for' giving effect to the policy of Part. IV.
Nor was it intended that defects in Part III
could not be cured or that possible errors in judicial interpretations of Part
III could not be rectified by constitutional amendments. [913 D-E] (viii) It
cannot be said that the people in exercise of their sovereign power have placed
the fundamental rights beyond the reach of the amending power. The people
acting through the Constituent Assembly reserved for themselves certain rights
and liberties and ordained that they shalt not be curtailed by ordinary
legislation. But the people by the same Constitution also authorised the
Parliament to make amendments to the Constitution. In exercise of the amending
power the Parliament has ample authority to, abridge or take away the
fundamental rights under Part III [915 B-C] Merely because of possibility of
abuse, the power cannot be denied. [916 H] Webb v. Outrim, [1907] A.C. 81 and
amalgamated Society of Engineers'. The Adelaide Steamship Company Limited &
Ors.
28 C.L.R. 129, referred to.
(ix) The main part of Art. 368 gives the
power to amend or make changes in the Constitution. A change is not necessarily
an improvement. Normally the change is made with the object of making an
improvement but the experiment may fail to achieve the purpose. [916 A]
Livermore v. E. G. Waite, 102 Cal. 113-25 L.R.A. 312 and National Prohibition
case. 253 U.S. 350, referred to.
77 5 (x) The best exposition of the
Constitution is that which it has received from contemporaneous judicial
decisions and enactments. No one in Parliament doubted the proposition that
fundamental rights could be amended, when the First Amendment Act of 1951 was
passed. The concept of amenability was upheld in S. Krishnan & Ors. v.
State of Madras [1951] S.C.R. 621 decided in 1951,'in Sankari Prasad decided in
1952 and Sajjan Singh decided in 1964. [918 C-D] (xi) There is no provision in
the Constitution for calling a convention for its revision or far submission of
any proposal for amendment to the referendum. [918 G] (xii) The impugned
amendments affected Arts. 226 and 245 only indirectly and did not require
ratification under the proviso to Art. 168. [919 D-H] In validating the
impugned laws Parliament was not encroaching on-.the State List. It was only
validating the said laws and such constitutional validating was within its competence.
[920 C-E] (xiii) The abolition of Zamindari was a necessary reform.
It is the First Constitution Amendment Act
that made this reform possible., No legal argument' can restore the outmoded
feudal Zamindari system.What has been done cannot be undone. The battle for the
put is lost. [921 B-C] If the First Fourth, Sixteenth & Seventeenth
Amendments Acts are void they do not legally exist from their inception.
They cannot be, valid from 1951 to 1967 and
invalid thereafter. To say that they were valid in the past and Will be invalid
in the future is to amend the.Constitution.
Such a naked power of amendment is not given
to the Judges and therefore the doctrine of prospective overruling cannot be,
adopted. [921 D-E] It is not possible to say that the First and Fourth
Amendments though originally valid have now been validated by acquiescence. If
they infringe Art. 13(2) they were void from their inception. If these amendments
are validated by acquiescence the Seventeenth Amendment is equally validated.
[921 F; 922 B] (xv) The contention that Dr.
Ambedkar did not regard the fundamental rights as amendable is not supported by
the speeches in the' Constituent Assembly. [922 C-D] Per Ramaswami J.(i) In a
written Constitution the amendment of the Constitution is a substantive
constituent act which, is made in the exercise of the sovereign power through a
predesigned procedure unconnected with ordinary legislation.
The amending power in Art. 368 is hence sui
generis and cannot be compared to the law making power of Parliament pursuant
to Art. 246 read with Lists II and Ill. It follows that the expression 'law' in
Art. 13(2) cannot be construed as including an amendment of the Constitution
which is achieved by Parliament in exercise of its sovereign constituent power
but must mean law made by Parliament in its legislative capacity under Art. 246
read 'with I List I and III of the 7th Schedule. It is also clear on the same
line of reasoning that law in Art. 13(2) cannot be construed so as to include
"law' made by Parliament under Arts. 4, 169, 392, 5th Schedule Part 1 and
6th Schedule para 21. The amending power of Parliament exercised under these
Articles stands on the same pedestal as the constitutional amend ment made
under Art. 368 so far as Art. 13(2) is concerned. [930 H 931 E] (ii) The
language of Art. 368 is perfectly general and empowers Parliament to amend the
Constitution without any exception whatsoever.
776 The use of the word 'fundamental' to
describe the rights in Part III and the word 'guaranteed' in Art. 32 cannot
lift the fundamental rights above the Constitution itself [931 F, H] (iii) It
is unreasonable to suggest that what Art. 368 provides is only the mechanics of
the procedure for amendment and not the power to amend. The significant fact
that a separate part has been devoted in the Constitution for "amendment
of the constitution" and there is only one Article in that Part shows that
both the power and the procedure to amend are enacted in Art. 368. Again the
words "the Constitution shall stand amended in accordance with the terms
of the Bill" in Art. 368 clearly contemplate and provide for the power to
amend after the requisite procedure has been followed. [932 C-E] (iv) The power
of constitutional amendment cannot fall within Arts. 246 and 248 read with item
97 of List I because it is illogical and a contradiction in terms to say that
the amending power can be exercised "subject to the provisions of the
Constitution" as the power under these articles must be. [933 B] (v) There
is no room for an implication in the construction ofArt. 368. If the
Constitution makers wanted certain basic features to be unamendable they would
have said so.
[933 G-H] State of West Bengal v. Union of
India, [1964] 1 S.C.R. 371 and In re The Berubari Union and Exchange of
Enclaves [1960] 3 S.C.R. 250, referred to.
The concepts of liberty and equality are
changing and dynamic and hence the notion of permanency or immutability cannot
be attached to any of the fundamental rights. The adjustment between freedom
and compulsion, between the rights of individuals and the social interest and
welfare must necessarily be a matter for changing needs and conditions. The
proper approach is therefore to look upon the fundamental rights of the
individual as conditioned by social responsibility, by the necessities of the
society, by the balancing of interests and not as pre-ordained and untouchable
private rights. [934 E-935 C] (vi) It must not be forgotten that neither the
rights in Art. 31 nor those in Art. 19 are absolute. The purposes for which
fundamental rights can be regulated which are specified in cls. (2) to (6)
could not have been assumed by the Constitution makers to be static and
incapable of expansion. It cannot be assumed that the Constitution makers
intended to forge a political strait-jacket for generations to come. Today at a
time when absolutes are discredited, it must not be too readily assumed that
there are basic features of the Constitution which shackle the amending power
and which take precedence over the general welfare of nation and the need for
agrarian and social reform. [936 B-937 C] (vii) In construing Art. 368 it is
essential to remember the nature and subject matter of that Article and to
interpret it subject a materies. The power of amendment is in point of quality
an adjunct of sovereignty. It is in truth the exercise of the highest sovereign
power in the State. if the amending power is an adjunct of sovereignty it does
not admit of any limitations. [937 D] (viii) If the fundamental rights are
unamendable and if Art. 368 does not include any such power it follows that the
amendment of, say, Art. 31 by insertions of Arts. 31A and 31B can only be made
by a violent revolution. It is doubtful if the proceedings of a new Constituent
Assembly that may be called will have any legal validity for if the 777
Constitution provides its own method of amendment, any other method will be
unconstitutional and void. [490 A-B] George S. Hawke v. Harvey C. Smith, 64
L.Ed. 871 and Feigenspan v. Bodine, 264 Fed. 186, referred to.
(ix) It is not permissible in the first place
to assume that in a matter of constitutional amendment there will be abuse of
power and then utilise it as a test for finding out the scope of the amending
power. In the last analysis political machinery and artificial limitations will
not protect the people from themselves. [941 F-G] State of West Bengal v. Union
of India, [1964] 1 S.C.R. 371 and American Federation of Labour v. American
Sash & Door Co. 335 U.S. 538, referred to.
(x) What the impugned Act purports to do is
not to make any and legislation but to protect and validate the legislative
measure passed by different State legislatures. This was within the legislative
competence of Parliament. [942 F] Leser v. Garnett, 258 U.S. 130, National
Prohibition Cases.
253 U.S. 350 and United States v. Sprague,
282 U.S. 716, referred to.
Articles 226 and 245. were not directly
affected by the impugned Act and therefore no ratification by the State
Legislatures was necessary. [942 D-H; 945 D] A. K. Gopalan v. State of Madras,
[1950] S.C.R. 88, Ram Singh & Ors. v. State of Delhi & Anr., [1951]
S.C.R. 451, Express Newspapers (Pvt.) Ltd. v. Union of India, [1959] S.C.R. 12,
Atiabari Tea Co. Ltd. v. State of Assam, [1961] 1 S.C.R. 809 and Naresh
Shridhar Mirajkar v. State of Maharashtra [1966] 3 S.C.R. 744, referred to.
(xi) Even on the assumption that the impugned
Act is unconstitutional the principle of stare decisis must be applied to the
present case and the plea made by the petitioners for reconsideration of Sankari
Prasad's case and Sajjan Singh's case must be rejected. [948 D-E] On the
landings it was not necessary to express an opinion on the doctrine of
prospective overruling of legislation.
[948 G-H] & ORIGINAL JURISDICTION: Writ
Petition No. 153 of 1966. (Under Article 32 of the Constitution of India for
enforcement of the Fundamental Rights) And Writ Petition No. 202 of 1966.
(Under Article 32 of the Constitution of
India for enforcement of the Fundamental Rights) And Writ Petition No. 205 of
1966.
(Under Article 32 of the Constitution of
India for enforcement of the Fundamental Rights) 778 In Writ Petition No. 153
of 1966.
R. V. S. Mani, S. K, Mehta and K. L. Mehta,
for the petitioners.
Niren,De, Additional Solicitor-General of
India,and R. N. Sachthey, for the Respondents.
Niren De, Additional Solicitor-General of
India,G.Rajagopal, and R. H. Dhebar,for Intervener Ng. 1.
S. D. Banerjee, Advocate-General for the
State of West Bengal, B. Sen and P. K. Bose,for Intervener No.2.
Lal Narain Sinha, Advocate-General for the
State of Bihar, Bajrang Saha, M. M. Gajadhar, K. M. K. Nair, D. P. Singh, M. K.
Ramamurthi, R. K. Garg, S. C.. Agarwala and G. D. Gupta, for Intervener No. 3.
Mohan Kumaramangalam., Advocate-General for
the State of Madras, B. Ramamurthi and A. V. Rangam, for Intervener No. V. D.
Mahajan and R. H. Dhebar, for Intervener No., 5.
K. L. Mishra, Advocate-General for the State
of Uttar Pradesh, and O. P. Rana, for Intervener No., 6.
V. A. Seyid Muhamad, Advocate-General for the
State of Kerala, B. R. L. Iyengar, A. G. Pudissery, for Intervener No. 7.
Naunit Lal, for Intervener No. 8.
K. B. Mehta, for Intervener No. 9.
P. Ram Reddy and T. V. R. Tatachari, for
Intervener No. 10.
M. C. Stealvad, B. R. L. Iyengar and R. H.
Dhebar, for Inter-vener No. 11.
R. Thiagarajan, for Intervener No. 12.
D. N. Mukherjee, for Interveners Nos. 13 and
19 to 21.
E. Udayairatnam, S. S. Dalal and D. D.
Sharma, for Interveners Nos. 14 and 15.
R. K Garg, D.. P. Singh, M. K. Ramamurthi, S.
C. Agarwala, G. D. Gupta and K. M. K. Nair' for Intervener No. 16.
'K. Parasaran and K. R. Chaudhuri, for
Intervener No. 17.
Basudev Prasad, K. Parasaran and K. R.
Chaudhuri, for Intervener No. 18.
Basudev-Prasad, K. Rajendra Chaudhuri, K. R.
Chaudhuri and S. N. Prasad, for Interveners Nos. 22 to 24.
779 in Writ Petition No. 202 of 1966.
M.K. Nambyar, K. B. Jinaraja Hegde, N. A.,
Subramaniam, Bhuvanesh Kumari, O. C. Mathur, J. B. Dadachanji and Ravinder
Narain, for the Petitioner.
H. R. Gokhale, B. P.. G. K. Achar, K. H.
Dhebar, R. N. Sachthey and S. P. Nayyar, for Respondent No. 1.
Niren De, Additional Solicitor-General, N. S.
Bindra and R. N. Sachthey, for Respondent No. 2.
A. K. Sen, F. S. Nariman, M. L. Bhakte, S. I.
Thakere, J.
B.
Dadachanji, O. C. Mathur and Ravinder Narain,
for Intervener No. 1.
N. A. Palkhiwala, F. S. Nariman, M. L.
Bhakte, D. M.
Popat,0. P. Malhotra, J. B. Dadachanji, O. C.
Mathur and Ravinder Narain, for Intervener No. 2.
D. M., Parulekar B. Dutta, J. B. Dadachanji,
O. C. Mathur and Ravinder Narain, for Intervener No.3.
In Writ Petition No. 205 of 1966.
M. K. Nambyar, K. B. Jinaraja Hegde, N. A.
Subramaniam, Bhuvanesh Kumari, O. C. Mathur, J. B. Dadachanji and Ravinder
Narain, for the Petitioner.
H. R. Gokhale, B. R. G. K. Achar, R. H.
Dhebar and S. P. Nayyar, for Respondent No. 1.
S. G. Patwardhan, D. M. Parulekar, B. Dutta,
S. K. Dhelika,
1. B. Dadachanji, O. C. Mathur and Ravinder
Narain, for the Intervener.
The Judgment Of SUBBA RAO, C.J., SHAH, SIKRI,
SHELAT and VAIDIALINGAM, JJ. was delivered by SUBBA RAO, C.I. According to this
Judgment-(i) the power to amend the Constitution is not to be found in Art. 368
but in Arts. 245, 246 and 248 read with Entry 97 of List 1; (ii) the amending
power can.
not be used to abridge or take away the
fundamental rights guaranteed in Part III of the Constitution; (iii) a law
amending the Constitution is "Law" within the meaning of Art. 13(2)
and (iv). the First, Fourth and Seventeenth Amendments though they abridged fundamental
rights were valid in the past on the basis of earlier decisions of this Court
and continue to be valid for the future. On the application of the doctrine of
"prospective over-ruling", as enunciated in the judgment, the
decision will have only prospective operation and Parliament will have no power
to abridge or take away Fundamental Rights from the date of the judgment.
The Judgment of WANCHOO, BHARGAVA and MITTER,
JJ. was delivered by WANCHOO, J. According to this Judgment (i) the 780 power
of amending the Constitution resides in Art. 368 and not in Arts. 245, 246 and
248, read with Entry 97 of List 1;
(ii) there, are no restrictions on the power
if the procedure in Art. 368 is followed and all the Parts of the Constitution
including Part III, can be amended, (iii) an amendment of the Constitution is
not "'law" under Art.
13(2); and (iv) the doctrine of
"prospective overruling" cannot be applied in India.
HIDAYATULLAH, J. delivered a separate
judgment agreeing with SUBBA Rao, CJ. on the following two points: (i) that the
power to amend the Constitution cannot be used to abridge or take away
fundamental rights; and (ii) that a law amending the Constitution is
"law" under Art. 13 (2). He agrees With WANCHOO, J. that the power to
amend does not reside in Arts.
245 and 248 read wish Entry 97 of List 1.
Art. 368, according to him, is sui generis
and procedural and the procedure when correctly followed, results in an
amendment. He does not rely on the doctrine of "prospective
overruling". As regards the First, Fourth and Seventh Amendments, these
having long enured and been acquiesced in, he does not treat the question of
their validity as being before him. As regards the Seventeenth Amendment he
finds sufficient support for it in the Constitution as amended by the First,
Fourth and Seventh Amendments and holds that the new definition of
"estate", introduced by the Amendment, though it is "law"
under Art. 13 (2) and is an inroad into fundamental rights, is beyond the reach
of the courts because it falls within the word "law" in Arts. 31 (1),
(2), 2A and 31A(1). He, however, declares section 3 of the Seventeenth
Amendment Act ultra vires the amending process as an illegitimate exercise of
the amending power.
[BACHAWAT and RAMASWAMI, JJ. delivered
separate judgments concurring with WANCHOO, J.] Subbarao, C.J. These three writ
petitions raise the important question of the validity of the Constitution
(Seventeenth Amendment) Act, 1964.
Writ Petition No. 153 of 1966, is filed by
the petitioners therein against the State of Punjab and the Financial
Commissioner, Punjab. The petitioners are the son, daughter and granddaughters
of one Henry Golak Nath, who died on July 30, 1953. The Financial Commissioner,
in revision against the order made by the Additional Commissioner, Jullundur
Division, held by an order dated January 22, 1962 that an area of 418 standard
acres and 9-1/4 units was surplus in the hands of the petitioners under the
provisions of the Punjab Security of Land Tenures Act X of 1953, read with s.
10-B thereof. The petitioners, alleging that
the relevant provisions of the said Act where under the said area was 781
declared surplus were void on the ground that they infringed their rights under
cls. (f) and (g) of Art. 19 and Art. 14 of the Constitution, filed a writ in
this Court under Art.
32 of the Constitution for a direction that
the Constitution (First Amendment) Act 1951, Constitution (Fourth Amendment)
Act, 1955, Constitution (Seventeenth Amendment) Act, 1964, insofar as they
affected their fundamental rights were unconstitutional and inoperative and for
a direction that s.
10-B of the said Act X of 1953 was void as
violative of Arts. 14 and 19 (1) (f) and (g) of the Constitution.
Writ Petitions Nos. 202 and 203 of 1966 were
filed by different petitioners under Art. 32 of the Constitution for a
declaration that the Mysore Land Reforms Act (Act 10 of 1962) as amended by Act
14 of 1965, which fixed ceilings on land holdings and conferred ownership of
surplus lands on tenants infringed Arts. 14, 19 and 31 of the Constitution and,
therefore, was unconstitutional and void.
The States of Punjab and Mysore, inter alia,
contended that the said Acts were saved from attack on the ground that they
infringed the fundamental rights of the petitioners by reason of the Constitution
(Seventeenth Amendment) Act, 1964, which, by amending Art. 31-A of the
Constitution and including the said two Arts in the 9th Schedule thereto, had
placed them beyond attack.
In Writ Petition No. 153 of 1966, 7 parties
intervened. In Writ Petition No. 202 of 1966 one party intervened. In addition,
in the first petition, notice was given to the Advocates General of various
States. A11 the learned counsel appearing for the parties, the Advocates
General appearing for the States and the learned counsel for the interveners
have, placed their respective viewpoints exhaustively before us. We are
indebted to all of them for their thorough preparation and clear exposition of
the difficult questions of law that were raised in the said petitions.
At the outset it would be convenient to place
briefly the respective contentions under different heads : (1) The Constitution
is intended to be permanent and, therefore, it cannot be amended in a way which
would injure, maim or destroy its indestructible character. (2) The word
"amendment" implies such an addition or change within the lines of
the original instrument as will effect an improvement or better carry out the
purpose for which it was framed and it cannot be so construed as to enable the
Parliament to destroy the permanent character of the Constitution. (3) The
fundamental rights are a part of the basic structure of the Constitution and,
therefore, the said power can be exercised only to preserve rather than destroy
the essence of those rights. (4) The limits on the power to amend are implied
in Art. 368, for the 782 expression "amend" has a limited meaning.
The wide phraseo-logy used in the Constitution in other Articles, such as
"repeal" and "re-enact" indicates that art. 368 only
enables a modification of the Articles within the framework of the Constitution
and a destruction of them. (5) The debates in the Constituent Assembly,
particularly the speech of Mr. Jawahar Lal Nehru, the first PA= Minister of
India, and the reply of Dr. Ambedkar, who piloted the Bill disclose clearly
that it was never the intention of the makers of the Constitution by putting in
Art. 368 to enable the Parliament to repeal the fundamental rights, the
circumstances under which the amendment moved by Mr. H. V. Kamath, one of the
members of Constituent Assembly, was withdrawn and Art. 368 was finally
adopted, support the contention that amendment of Part II, is outside the scope
of Art. 368. (6) Part III of the Constitution is a self-contained Code. and its
provisions are elastic enough to meet all reasonable requirements of changing
situations. (7) The power to amend is sought to be derived from three sources,
namely, (i) by implication under Art. 368 itself; The procedure to amend
culminating in the amendment of the Constitution necessarily implies that
power, (ii) the power and ,the limits of the power to amend are implied in the
Articles sought to be amended, and (iii) Art. 368 only lays down the procedure
to amend, but the power to amend is only the legislative power conferred on the
Parliament under Arts. 245, 246 and 248 of the Constitution. (8) The definition
of "law" in Art. 13(2) of the Constitution includes every branch of
law, statutory, constitutional, etc.,' and therefore, the power to amend in
whichever branch it may be classified, if it takes away or abridges fundamental
rights would be void there under. (9) The impugned amendment detracts from the
jurisdiction of the High Court under Art. 226 of the Constitution and also the
legislative powers of the States and therefore it falls within the scope of the
proviso to Art. 368.
The said summary, though not exhaustive,
broadly gives the various nuances of the contentions raised by the learned
counsel, who question the validity of the 17th Amendment.
We have not noticed the other arguments of
Mr. Nambiar, which are peculiar to the Writ Petition No. 153 of 1966 as those
questions do not arise for decision, in the view we are taking on the common
questions.
On behalf of the Union and the States the
following points were pressed : (1) A Constitutional amendment is made in
exercise of the sovereign power and not legislative power of Parliament and,.
therefore, it partakes the quality and character of the Constitution itself.
(2) The real distinction is between a rigid and a flexible Constitution.
The distinction is based upon the express
limits of the amending power. (3) The provisions of Art.
783 368-axe clear and unequivocal and there
is no-scope for invoking implied limitations on that power: further the
doctrine of implied power has been rejected by the American courts and jurists.
(4) The object of the amending clause in a flexible Constitution is to enable
the Parliament to amend the Constitution in order to express the will of the
people according to the changing course of events and if amending power is
restricted by implied limitations, the Constitution itself might be destroyed
by revolution.
Indeed, it is a safety valve and an
alternative for a violent change by revolution. (5) There are no basic and
non-basic features of the Constitution; everything in the Constitution is basic
and it can be amended in order to help the future growth and progress of the
country. (6) Debates.
in the Constituent Assembly cannot be relied
upon for construing Art. 368 of the Constitution and even if-they can be, there
is nothing in the debates to prove, positively that fundamental rights were
excluded from amendment. (7) Most of the amendments are made out of political
necessity:
they involve, questions, such. as, how to
exercise power,, how to make the lot of the citizens better and the like and,
therefore, not being judicial questions, they are outside the court's
jurisdiction. (8) The language of Art. 368 is clear, categorical, imperative
and universal, on the other hand, the language of Art. 13(2) is such as to
admit qualifications or limitations and, therefore, the Court must construe
them in such a manner as that Article could not control Art. 368. (9) In order
to enforce the Directive Principles the Constitution was amended from time to
time and the great fabric of the Indian Union has been built since 1950 on the
basis that the Constitution could be amended and, therefore, any reversal of,
the previous I decisions would introduce economic chaos in our country and
that, therefore, the burden is very heavy upon the petitioners to establish
that the fundamental rights cannot be amended under Art. 368 of the
Constitution. (10) Art. 31A and the 9th Schedule do not affect the power of the
High Court under Art. 226 or the legislative power of the States though the
area of their operation is limited and, therefore, they do not fall within the
scope of the proviso to Art. 3 68.
The aforesaid contentions only represent a
brief summary of elaborate arguments, advanced by learned counsel. We shall
deal in appropriate context with the other points mooted before US.
It will be convenient to read the material
provisions of the Constitution at. this stage.
Article 13(1) (2) The State shall not make
any law which takes away or abridges the rights conferred by this part and any
law made in contravention of this clause shall, toy the extent of the
contravention, be void.
784 (3) In this article, unless the context
otherwise requires,(a) "law" includes any Ordinance, order, bye-law,
rule regulation, notification, custom or usage having in the territory of India
the force of law.
Article 31-A(1), Notwithstanding anything
contained in article 13, no law providing for, (a) the acquisition by the State
of any estate or of any rights therein or the extinguishment or modification of
any such rights, shall be deemed to be void on the ground that it is
inconsistent with, or takes away or abridges any of the rights conferred by
article 14, article 19 or article 31.
(2) (a) the expression "estate"
shall, in relation to any local area, have the same meaning as that expression
or it social equivalent has in the existing law relating to land tenure in
force in that area and shall also include, (ii) any land held under ryotwari
settlement, (iii) any land held or let for purposes of agriculture or for
purposes ancillary thereto......
Article 31-D. Without prejudice to the
generality of the provisions contained in article 31-A, none of the Acts and
Regulations specified in the Ninth Schedule nor any of the provisions thereof
shall be deemed to be void, or ever to have become void, on the ground that
such Act, Regulation or provision is inconsistent with, or takes away or
abridges any of the rights conferred by, any provisions of this Part, and not
withstanding any judgment decree or order of any court or tribunal to the
contrary, each of the said Acts and Regulations shall, subject to the power of
any competent Legislature to repeal or amend it, continue in force.
In the Ninth Schedule to the Constitution the
Mysore Land Reforms Act, 1961, (Mysore Act 10 of 1962) is included as item 51
and the Punjab Security of Land Tenures Act, 1953 (Punjab Act 10 of 1953) is
included as item 54. The definition of "estate" was amended and the
Ninth Schedule was amended by including therein the said two Acts by the
Constitution (Seventeenth Amendment) Act, 1964.
785 The result of the said amendments is that
both the said Acts dealingwith estates, within their wide definition introduced
by the Constitution (Seventeenth Amendment) Act, 1964, having been included in
the Ninth Schedule, are placed beyond any attack on the ground that their
provisions are inconsistent with or take away or abridge any of the rights
conferred by Part III of the Constitution. It is common case that if the Constitution
(Seventeenth Amendment) Act, 1964, was constitutionally valid, the said Acts
could not be impugned on any of the said grounds.
The question of the amendability of the
fundamental rights was considered by this Court earlier in two decisions, namely,
Sri Sankari Prasad Singh Deo v. Union of India and State of Bihar(1) and in
Sajjan Singh v. State of Rajasthan (2) In the former the validity of the
Constitution (First Amendment) Act, 1951, which inserted, inter alia, Arts.
31-A and 31-B in the Constitution, was questioned. That amendment was made
under Art. 368 of the Constitution by the Provisional Parliament. This Court
held that Parliament had power to amend Part III of the Constitution. The Court
came to that conclusion on two grounds, namely, (1) the word "law" in
Art. 13(2) was one made in exercise of legislative power and not constitutional
law made in exercise of constituent power; and (ii) there were two articles
(Arts.
13(2) and 368) each of which was widely
phrased and, therefore, harmonious construction required that one should be so
read as to be controlled and qualified by the other, and having regard to the
circumstances mentioned in the judgment Art. 13 must be read subject to Art.
368. A careful perusal of' the judgment indicates that the whole decision
turned upon an assumption that the expression "law" in Art 13(2) does
not include constitutional law and on that assumption an attempt was made to
harmonise Article 13 (2) and 368 of the Constitution.
The decision in Sajjan Singh's case(2) was
given in the context of the question of the validity of the Constitution
(Seventeenth Amendment) Act, 1964. Two questions arose in that case: (1)
Whether the amendment Act insofar it purported to take away or abridge the
rights conferred by Part III of the Constitution fell within the prohibition of
Art. 13(2) and (2) Whether Articles 31-A and 31-B sought to make changes in
Arts. 132, 136 or 226 or in any of the lists in the Seventh Schedule and
therefore the requirements of the proviso to Article 368 had to be satisfied.
Both the Chief Justice and Mudholkar, J. made it clear that the first
contention was not raised before the Court. The learned counsel appearing for
both the parties accepted the correctness of the decision in Sankari Prasad's
case(1) in that (1) [1952] S.C.R. 89,105.
(2) [1965] 1 S.C.R. 933, 946, 950, 959, 961,
963.
786 regard. Yet Gajendragadkar, C.J. speaking
for the majority ,agreed with the reasons given in Sankari Prasad's case(1) on
the first question and Hidayatullah and Mudholkar, JJ.
expressed their dissent from the-said view.
But all of them agreed, though for different reasons on the second question.
Gajendragadkar, C.J. speaking for himself,
Wanchoo and Raghubar Dayal, JJ. rejected the contention that Art. 368 did not
confer power on Parliament to take. away the fundamental rights guaranteed by
Part III. When a suggestion was made that the decision in the aforesaid case
should be reconsidered and reviewed, the learned Chief Justice though he
conceded that in a casewhere a decision had a significant impact on the
fundamental rights of citizens, the Court would be inclined to review its
earlier decision in the interests of the public good, he did not find
considerations of substantial and compelling character to do so in that case.
But after: referring to the reasoning given in Sankari Prasad's case(1) the;
learned Chief Justice observed "In our opinion , the expression
"amendment of the, Constitution" plainly and unambiguously means
amendment of all the provisions of the Constitution." Referring, to Art.
13 (2), he restated the same reasoning found in, the earlier decision and added
that if it was the intention of the Constitution-makers to save, fundamental
rights from the amending,process they should have taken the precaution of
making A-. clear provision in that regard. In short, the majority, speaking
through Gajendragadkar, C.L agreed that no case had been made, out for
reviewing the earlier decision and practically accepted the reasons given in
the-earlier decision. Hidyatullah J. speaking for himself, observed "But I
make it clear that I must not be understood to have subscribed to the view that
the word "law" in Art. 13(2) does not control constitutional
amendments., I reserve my opinion on that case for I apprehend that it depends
on how wide is the "law"in that Article." After giving his
reasons for doubting the correctness of the reasoning given in Sankari Prasad's
case(1), the learned Judge concluded thus :
"I would require stronger reasons than
those given in Sankari Prasad's case(1) to make me accept the view that
Fundamental Rights were not really fundamental but were intended to be within
the powers of amendment in common with the other parts of the Constitution and
without the concurrence of the States." (1) [1952] S.C.R. 89.
787 The. learned Judge continued "The
Constitution gives so many assurances in Part III that it would be difficult to
think that they were the playthings of a special majority." Mudholkar, J.
was positive that the result of a legislative action of a legislature could not
be other than "law" and, therefore, it seemed to him that the fact
that the legislation dealt with the amendment of a provision of the
Constitution would not make, its results any the less a 'law".
He further pointed out that Art. 368 did not
say that whenever Parliament made an amendment to the Constitution it assumed a
different capacity from that of a constituent body. He also brought out other
defects in the line of reasoning adopted in Sankari Prasad's case(1). It will,
therefore,be seen-that the correctness of the decision in Sankari Prasad's
case(1) was not questioned in Sajjan Singh's case(2) Though it was not
questioned, three of the learned Judges agreed with the view expressed therein,
but two learned Judges were inclined to take a different view.
But, as that question was not raised, the
minority agreed with the conclusion, arrived at by the majority on the question
whether the Seventeenth Amendment Act was, covered by the proviso. to Art. 368
of the Constitution. The conflict between the majority and the minority in
Sajjan's Singh's case(1) falls to be resolved in this case. The said conflict
and, the great importance of the question raised is the justification for-..the
Constitution of the larger Bench., The decision in Sankri Prasad's case(1) was
assumed to be correct in subsequent decisions of this Court. See S.
Krishnan v. State of Madras(1), The State-'
of West Bengal v. Anwar All Sarkar(1) and Basheshar Nath v. The Commissioner of
Income-tax, Delhi and Rajasthan(5). But nothing turns upon that fact, as the
correctness of the derision was not questioned-. in those cases.
A correct appreciation of the scope and the
place of fundamental rights in our Constitution will give its the right
perspective for solving the problem presented before us, Its scope cannot be
appreciated unless we have a conspectus of the Constitution, its objects. and
its machinery to achieve those object. The objective sough tto be achieved by
the Constitution is declared in sonorous terms. in its preamble which reads
"We the people of India having solemnly resolved to constitute India into
a Sovereign, Democratic, Republic and to secure to all its citizens justice.
liberty. equality. and fraternity-.
(1) [1952] S.C.R. 89 (3) [1951] S.C.R. 621 at
page 652.
(2) [1965] 1 S.C.R.933.
(4) [1952] S.C.R. 284, 366.
(5) [1959] Supp. 1 S.C.R. 528,563.
788 It contains in a nutshell, its ideals and
its aspirations.
The preamble is not a platitude but the, mode
of its realisation is worked out in detail in the Constitution.
The Constitution brings into existence
different constitutional entities, namely, the Union, the States and the Union
Territories. It creates three major instruments of power, namely, the
Legislature, the Executive and the Judiciary. It demarcates their jurisdiction
minutely and expects them to exercise their respective powers without
overstepping their limits. They should function within the spheres allotted to
them. Some powers overlap and some are superseded during emergencies. The mode
of resolution of conflicts and conditions for supersession are also prescribed.
In short, the scope of the power and the-manner of its exercise are regulated
by law. No authority created under the Constitution is supreme; the Constitution
is supreme; and all the authorities function under the supreme law of the land.
The rule of law under the Constitution has a glorious content. It embodies the.
modem concept of law evolved over the centuries. It empowers the Legislatures
to make laws in respect of matters enumerated in the 3 Lists annexed to
Schedule VII. In Part IV of the Constitution, the Directive Principles of State
Policy are laid down. It enjoins it to bring about a social order in which
justice, social. economic and political-shall inform all the institutions of
national life. It directs it to work for an egalitarian society where there is
no concentration of wealth, where there is plenty, where there is equal
opportunity for all, to education, to work, to livelihood'.
and where there is social justice. But,
having regard to the past history of our country, it could not implicitly
believe the representatives of the people, for uncontrolled and unrestricted
power might lead to an authoritarian State.
It, therefore, preserves the natural rights
against the State encroachment and constitutes the higher judiciary of the
State as the sentinel of the said rights and the balancing wheel between the
rights, subject to social control. In short, the fundamental rights, subject to
social control, have been incorporated in the rule of law.
That is brought about by an interesting
process. In the implementation of the Directive Principles, Parliament or the
Legislature of a State makes laws in respect of matter or matters allotted to
it. But the higher Judiciary tests their validity on certain objective
criteria, namely, (i) whether the appropriate Legislature has the legislative
competency to make the law; (ii) whether the said law infringes any of the
fundamental rights; (iii) even if it Infringement the freedoms under Art. 19,
whether the infringement only amounts to "reasonable restriction" on
such rights in "public interest." By this process of scrutiny, the
court maintains the validity of only such laws as keep a just balance between
freedoms and social control.
The duty of reconciling fundamental rights in
Art. 19 and the laws of social control is cast upon the courts 789 and the
touchstone or the standard is contained in the said two expressions. The
standard is an elastic one; it varies with time, space and condition. What is
reasonable under certain circumstances may not be so under different
circumstances. The constitutional philosophy of law is reflected in Parts-1111
and IV of the Constitution. The rule of law under the Constitution serves the
needs of the people without unduly infringing their rights. It recognizes the
social reality and tries to adjust itself to it from-time, to time avoiding the
authoritarian pat@.
EKery institution or political party that
functions under the Constitution must accept it; otherwise it has no place
under the Constitution.
Now, what are the fundamental rights ? They
are embodied in Part III of the Constitution and they may be classified thus :
(i) right to equality, (ii) right to freedom, (iii)right against exploitation,
(iv) right to freedom of religion, (v) cultural and educational rights, (vi)
right to property, and (vii) right to constitutional remedies. They are the
rights of the people preserved by our Constitution. "Fundamental rights"
are the modern name for what have been traditionally known as "natural
rights". As one author puts: "they are moral rights which every human
being everywhere at all times ought to have sum y because of the fact that in
contradistinction with ot moral." They are the primordial mint of human
personality. man to chalk out his own life in is rational and ry for the
developrights which enable a he likes best. Our Constitution, in addition to
the well-known fundamental rights, also included the rights of the minorities, untouchables
and other backward communities, in such rights.
After having declared the fundamental rights,
our Constitution says that all laws in force in the territory of India
immediately before the commencement of the Constitution, insofar as they are inconsistent
with the said rights, are, to the extent of such inconsistency, void. The
Constitution also enjoins the State not to make any law which takes away or
abridges the said rights and declares such laws, to the extent of such
inconsistency, to be void.
As we have stated earlier, the only
limitation c)n the freedom enshrined in Art. 19 of the Constitution is that
imposed by a valid law rating as a reasonable restriction in the interests of
the public.
It will, therefore, be seen that fundamental
rights are given transcendental position under our Constitution and are kept
beyond the reach of Parliament. At the same time Parts 1111 and V constituted
an integrated scheme forming a self-contained code. The scheme is made so
elastic that all the Directive ' Principles of State Policy can reasonably be
enforced 'without taking -up. Cl/67-5 790 away or abridging the fundamental
rights. While recognizing the immutability of fundamental rights, subject to
social control, the Constitutional itself provides for the suspension or the
modification of fundamental rights under specific circumstances, for instance,
Art. 33 empowers Parliament to modify the rights conferred by Part III in their
application to the members of the armed forces, Art.
34 enables it to impose restrictions on the
rights conferred by the said parts while martial law is in force in an area,
Art. 35 confers the power on it to make laws with respect to any of the matters
which under clause (3) of Art. 16, Clause (3) of Art. 32, Art. 33 and Art. 34
may be provided for by law. The non-obstante clause with which the last article
opens makes it clear that all the other provisions of the Constitution are
subject to this provision. Article 32 makes the right to move the Supreme
Court, by appropriate proceedings for the enforcement of the rights conferred
by the said Parts a guaranteed right. Even during grave emergencies Art. 358
only suspends the provisions of Art. 19; and Art. 359 enables the President by
order to declare the right to move any court for the enforcement of such of the
rights conferred by Part III as may be mentioned in that order to be suspended;
that is to say, even during emergency, only Art. 19 is suspended temporarily
and all other rights are untouched except those specifically suspended by the
President.
In the Book "Indian
Constitution-Corerstone of a Nation" by Granville Austin, the scope origin
and the object of fundamental rights have been graphically stated. Therein the
learned author says :
"........ the core of the commitment to
the social revolution lies in Parts III and IV, in the Fundamental Rights and
fit the Directive Principles of State Policy. These are the conscience of the
Constitution." Adverting to the necessity for incorporating fundamental
rights in a Constitution, the learned author says That a declaration of rights
had assumed such importance was not surprising; India was a land of
communities, of minorities, racial, religious, linguistic, social and caste.
For India to become a state these minorities had to agree to be governed both
at the centre and in the provinces by fellow Indian-members, perhaps, of
another minority-and not by a mediatory third power, the British. On both
psychological and political, rounds., therefore-, the demand for written right
rights would provide tangible safeguards, against oppression-proved
overwhelming.
791 Motilal Nehru, who presided over the
Committee called for by the Madras Congress resolution, in May, 1928 observed
in his report :
"It is obvious that our first care
should be to have our Fundamental Rights guaranteed in a manner which will not
permit their withdrawal under any circumstances .... Another reason why great
importance attached to a Declaration of Rightsis the unfortunate existence of
communal differences in the country. Certain safeguards are necessary to create
and establish a sense of security among those who look upon each other with
distrust and suspicion. We could dot, better secure the full enjoyment of
religious and communal rights to all communities than by including them among
the basic principles of the Constitution." Pandit Jawaharlal Nehru, on
April 30, 1947 in proposing for the adoption of the Interim Report on
Fundamental Rights, said thus :
"A fundamental right should be looked
upon, not from the point of view of any particular difficulty of the moment,
but as something that you want to make permanent in the Constitution. The other
matter should be looked upon-however important it might be-not from this
permanent and fundamental point of view, but from the more temporary point of
view." Pandit Jawaharlal Nehru, who was Prime Minister at that time and.
who must have had an effective voice in the framing of the Constitution, made
this distinction between fundamental rights and other provisions of the
Constitution, namely, the former were permanent and the latter were amendable.
On September 18, 1949 Dr. Ambedkar in speaking on the amendment proposed by Mr.
Kamath to Art. 304 of the Draft Constitution corresponding to the present Art.
368, namely, "Any provision of this Constitution may be amended, whether
by way of variation, addition or repeal, in the manner provided in this
article", said thus "Now, what is it we do ? We divide the articles
of the Constitution under three categories. The first category is the one which
consists of-articles which can be amended by Parliament by a bare majority. The
second set of articles are articles which require two-thirds majority. If the
future Parliament wishes to amend any particular article which is not mentioned
in Part III or article 304, all that is necessary for them is to have
two-thirds majority. Then they can amend it." 792 Therefore, in Dr.
Ambedkar's view the fundamental rights were so important that they could not be
amended in the manner provided by Art. 304 of the Draft Constitution, which
corresponds to the present Art. 368.
We have referred to the speeches of Pandit
Jawaharlal Nehru and Dr. Ambedkar not with a view to interpret the provisions
of Art. 368, which we propose to do on its own terms, but only to notice the
transcendental character given to the fundamental rights by two of the
important architects of the Constitution.
This Court also noticed the paramountcy of
the fundamental rights in many decisions. In A. K. Gopalan v. State of Madras(1)
they are described as "paramount', in State of Madras v. Smt. Champakam
Dorairajan(2) as "sacrosanct", in Pandit M. S. M. Sharma v. Shri Sri
Krishna Sinha(s) as "rights reserved by the people', in Smt. Vijam Bai v.
State of Uttar Pradesh(1) as "inalienable and inviolable",and in
other cases as "transcendental". The minorities regarded them as the
bedrock of their political existence and the majority considered them as a
guarantee for their way of life. This, however, does not mean that the problem
is one of mere dialectics. The Constitution has given by its scheme a place of
permanence to the fundamental freedoms.
In giving to themselves the Constitution, the
people have reserved the fundamental freedoms to themselves. Article 13 merely
incorporates that reservation. That Article is however not the source of the
protection of fundamental rights but the expression of the reservation. The
importance attached to the fundamental freedoms is so transcendental that a
bill enacted by a unanimous vote of all the members of both the Houses is
ineffective to derogate from its guaranteed exercise. It is not what the
Parliament regards at a given moment as conducive to the public benefit, but
what Part III declares protected, which determines the ambit of the freedom.
The incapacity of the Parliament therefore in exercise of its amending power to
modify, restrict or impair fundamental freedoms in Part III arises from the
scheme of the Constitution and the nature of the freedoms.
Briefly stated, the, Constitution declares
certain rights as fundamental laws infringing the said rights of social control
infringing the said power on Parliament and the them in specified
circumstances; if the decisions in San Prasad's case(1) and Sajjan Singh's
case(1) laid down the correct law, it enables the same Parliament to abrogate
them with one stroke, provided the party in power singly or in combination with
other parties commands the neces(1) [1950] S.C.R. 88 198.
(3) [1959] Supp. 1 S.C.R. 806.
(5) [1952] S.C.P. 89,105.
(2) [1951] S.C.R, 525.
(4) [1963] 1 S.C.R. 778.
(6) [1965] S. C. R. 933.
793 sary majority. While articles of less
significance would require consent of the majority of the States, fundamental
rights can. be dropped without such consent. While a single fundamental right
cannot be abridged or taken away by the entire Parliament unanimously voting to
that effect, a two thirds' majority can do away with all the fundamental
rights. The entire super structure built with precision and high ideals may
crumble at one false step. Such a conclusion would attribute unreasonableness
to the makers of the Constitution, for, in that event they would be speaking in
two voices. Such an intention cannot be attributed to the makers of the
Constitution unless the provisions of the Constitution compel us to do so.
With this background let us proceed to
consider the provisions of Art. 368, vis-a-vis Art. 13(2) of the Constitution.
The first question is whether amendment of
the Constitution under Art. 368 is "law" within the meaning of Art.
13(2).
The marginal note to Art. 368 describes that
article as one prescribing the procedure for amendment. The article in terms
only prescribes various procedural steps in the matter of amendment: it shall
be initiated by the introduction of a bill in either House of Parliament; it
shall be passed by the prescribed majority in both the Houses; it shall then be
presented to the President for his assent; and upon such assent the
Constitution shall stand amended. The article assumes the power to amend found
else and says that it shall be exercised in the manner laid down therein. The
argument that the completion of the procedural AM culminates in the exercise of
the power to amend may be subtle but does not carry conviction. If that was the
intention of the provisions, nothing prevented the makers of the Constitution
from stating that the Constitution may be amended in the manner suggested.
Indeed, whenever the Constitution sought to confer a special power to amend on
any authority it expressly said so : (See Arts. 4 and 392). The alternative
contention that the said power shall be implied either from Art. 368 or from
the nature of the articles sought to be amended cannot be accepted, for the
simple reason that the doctrine of necessary implication cannot be invoked if
there is an express sion or unless but for such implication the article will no
necessity to imply any plenary power to make any Constitution subject to the
Uninfluenced by any foreign doctrines let us look at the provisions of our Constitution.
Under Art. 245, "subject to the provisions of the Constitution, Parliament
may make laws for the whole or any part of the territory of India........
Article 246 demarcates the matters in respect
of which Parliament and State 794 Legislatures may make laws. In the field
reserved for Parliament there is Entry 97 which empowers it to make laws in
respect of " any other matter not enumerated in Lists II and III including
any tax not mentioned in either of those lists." Article 248 expressly
states that Parliament has exclusive power to make any law with respect to any
matter not enumerated in the Concurrent List ,or State List. It is, therefore,
clear that the residuary power of legislation is vested in Parliament. Subject
to the argument based upon the alleged nature of the amending power as
understood by jurists in other countries, which we shal consider at a later
stage, it cannot be contended, and indeed, it was not contended, that the
Constituent Assembly, if it were so minded, could not have conferred an express
legislative power on Parliament to amend the Constitution by ordinary
legislative process. Articles 4 and 169, and para 7 of the 5th Schedule and
para 21 of the 6th Schedule have expressly conferred such power. There is,
therefore, no inherent Inconsistency between legislative process and the
amending one. Whether in the field of a constitutional law or statutory law
amendment can be brought about only by law.
The residuary power of Parliament, unles
there is anything contrary in the ,Constitution, certainly takes in the power
to amend the Constitution. It is said that two Articles 'indicate the contrary
intention. As Art. 245, the argument proceeds, is subject to the provisions of
the Constitution, every law of amendment will necessarily be inconsistent with
the articles sought to be amended. 'Ibis is an argument in a circle. Can it be
said reasonably that a law amending an article is inconsistent with the article
amended ? If an article of the Constitution expressly says that it cannot be amended,
a law cannot be made amending it, as the power of Parliament to make a law is
subject to the said Article. It may-well be that in a given case such a
limitation may also necessarily be implied. The limitation in Art. 245 is in
respect of the power to make a law and not of the content of the law made
Within the scope of its power. The second criticism is based upon Art. 39 of
the Constitution. That provision confers power on the President to remove
difficulties; in the circumstances mentioned in that provision, he can by order
direct that the Constitution shall during such period as may be specified in
that order have effect subject to such adaptations, whether by way of
modification, addition ,or omission, as he may deem to be necessary or expedient.
The argument is that the President's power, though confined to a temporqry
period,is co-extensive with legislative power and if the power to amend is a
legislative power it would have to be held that the President can amend the
Constitution in terms of Art.
368. Apart from the limited scope of Art.
392, which is intended only for the purpose of removing difficulties and for
bringing about a smooth transition, an order made by the Presi795 dent cannot
attract Art. 368, as the amendment contemplated by that provision can be
initiated only by the introduction of a bill in the Parliament. There is no
force in either of the two criticisms.
Further, there is, internal evidence in the
Constitution itself which indicates that amendment to the Constitution is a
"law" within the meaning of Art. 245. Now, what is "law"
under the Constitution ? It is not denied that in its comprehensive sense it
includes constitutional law and the law amending the Constitution is
constitutional law. But Art. 13(2) for the purpose of that Article gives an
inclusive definition. It does not exclude Constitutional law. It prima facie takes
in constitutional law. Article 368 itself gives the necessary clue to the
problem. The amendment can be initiated by. the introduction of a bill;
it shall be passed by the two Houses; it
shall' receive the assent of the President. These are well-known procedural
steps in the process of law-making : Indeed this Court in Sankari Prasads
case(1) brought out this idea in clear terms.. It said "in the first
place, it is provided that the amendment must be initiated by the introduction
of a "bill in either House of Parliament' a familiar feature of Parliament
procedure (of Article 107(1) which says "A bill may originate in either
House of Parliament"). 'Then, the bill must be "Passed in each
House,"-just what Parliament does when it is called upon to exercise its
normal legislative function Article 107(2)1; and finally, the bull thus passed
must be "president to the President" for his "assent",
again a parliamentary process through which every bill must pass before it can
reach the statute-book, (Article 1 1 1 ). We thus find that each of the
component units of Parliament is to play its allotted part in bringing about an
amendment to the Constitution. We have already seen that Parliament effects
amendments of the first class mentioned above by going through the same
three-fold procedure but with a simple majority. The fact that a different
majority in the same body is required for effecting the second and third categories
of 1 amendments make the amending agency a different body." In the same
decision it is pointed out that Art. 368 is not a complete code in respect of
the procedure. This Court said "There are gaps in the procedure as to how
and after what notice a bill is to be introduced, how it is to be passed by
each House and how the President's assent is to be obtained. Having provided
for the Constitution of a Parliament and prescribed a certain procedure for the
conduct of its ordinary legislative business to be supplemented by rules made
by each House (Article 118), the makers of the Constitution must be taken to
have intended Parliament to follow that procedure, so far as they may be
applicable consistently with the express provision of Art.
368, when they have entrusted to it the power
of =ending the Constitution (1) ( 1 952) S.C. R. 89.
796." The House of the People made rules
providing procedure for amendments, the same as for other Bills with the
addition of certain special provisions viz., Rules 155, 156, 157 and 158. If
amendment is intended to be something other than law, the constitutional
insistence on the said legislative process is unnecessary. In short, amendment
cannot be made otherwise than by following the legislative process. The fact
that there are other conditions, such as, a larger majority and in the case of
articles mentioned in the proviso a ratification by Legislatures is provided,
does not make the amendment any the less a law. The imposition of further
conditions is only a safeguard against hasty action or a protection to the
States, but does not change the Legislative character of the amendment.
This conclusion is reinforced by the other
articles of the Constitution. Article 3 enables Parliament by law to form now
States and alter areas, boundaries or the names of existing States. imposed
two, further conditions, of the President, and (ii) in therein, the views
expressed by the Legislatures. Notwithstanding the said conditions it cannot be
suggested that the expression "law" under the said Article is not one
made by the Legislative process. Under Art. 4, such a law can contain
provisions for amendment of Schedules I and IV indicating thereby that
amendments are only made by Legislative process. What is more, cl. (2) thereof
introduces a fiction to the affect that such a law shall not be deemed to be an
amendment to the Constitution.
This shows that the amendment is law and that
but for the fiction it would be an amendment within the meaning of Art.
368. Article 169 which empowers Parliament by
law to abolish or create Legislative Councils in States, para 7 of the 5th
Schedule and para 21 of the 6th Schedule which enable Parliament by law to
amend the said Schedules, also bring out the two ideas that the amendment is
law made by legislative process and that but for the fiction introduced it
would attract Article 368. That apart amendments under the said provisions can
be made by the Union Parliament by simple majority. That an amendment is made
only by legislative process with or without conditions will be clear if two
decisions of the Privy Council are considered in juxta-position. They are
McCawley v. The King(1) and The Bribery Commissioner v. Pedrick Rana singhe(2).
The facts in McCawley v. The King(1) were
these: In 1859 Queensland had been granted a Constitution in the terms of an
Order in Council made on June 6 of that year under powers derived by Her
Majesty from the Imperial Statute, 18 & 19 Vict.
(1) [1920] A.C. 691.
(2) [1964] W.L.R. 1301.
797 c. 54. The Order in Council had set up a
legislature for the territory, consisting of the Queen, a Legislative Council
and a. Legislative Assembly, and the law-making power was vested in Her Majesty
acting with the advice and consent of the Council and Assembly. Any laws could be
made for the "peace, welfare and good government of the Colony".
The said legislature of Queensland in the
year 1867 passed the Constitution Act of that year. Under that Act power was
given to the said legislature to make laws for "peace, welfare and good
Government of the Colony in all cases whatsoever". But, under s. 9 thereof
a two-thirds majority of the Council and of the Assembly %,as required as a
condition precedent to the validity of legislation altering the constitution of
the Council. The Legislature, therefore, had, except in the case covered by s.
9 of the Act, an unrestricted power to make laws. The Legislature passed a law
which conflicted with one of the existing terms of the Constitution Act. Lord
Birkenhead, L.C., upheld-the law, as the Constitution Act conferred an absolute
power upon the legislature to pass any law by majority even though it, in
substance, amended the terms of the Constitution Act.
In The Bribery Commissioner v. Pedrick
Ranasinghe(1), the facts are these : By section 29 of the Ceylon (Constitution)
Order in Council, 1946, Parliament shall have power to make laws for the,
"peace. order and good government" of the Island and in the exercise
of its power under the said section it may amend or repeal any of the provisions
of the Order in its application to the Island. The proviso to that section says
that no Bill for the amendment or repeal of any of the provisions of the Order
shall be presented for the Royal assent unless it has endorsed on it a
certificate under the hand of the Speaker that the number of votes cast in
favour thereof in the House of Representatives amounted to not less than
two-thirds of the whole number of members of the House. Under s. 55 of the said
Order the appointment of Judicial Officers was vested in the Judicial Service
Commission. But the Parliament under s. 41 of the Bribery Amendment Act, 1958,
provided for the appointment of the personnel of the Bribery Tribunals by the
Governor-General on the advice of the Minister of Justice. The said Amendment
Act was in conflict with the said s. 55 of the Order and it was passed without
complying with the terms of the proviso to s. 29 of the Order. The Privy
Council held that the Amendment Act was void. Lord Pearce, after considering
McCawley's case(2) made the following observations, at p. 1310 :
"........ a legislature has no power to
ignore, the conditions of law-making that are imposed by the (1) [1964] 2
W.L.R. 1301.
(2) [1920] A.C. 69 1.
798 instrument which itself regulates its
power to make law. This restriction exists independently of the , question
whether the legislature is sovereign, as is the legislature of Ceylon, or
whether the Constitution is "uncontrolled", as the Board held the
Constitution of Queensland to be.
Such a Constitution can, indeed, be altered
or amended by the legislature, if the regulating instrument so provides and if
the terms of those provisions are complied with........
It will be seen from the said judgments that
an amendment of the Constitution is made only by legislative process with
ordinary majority or with special majority, as the case may be. There.fore,
amendments either under Art. 368 or under other Articles ,axe made only by
Parliament by following the legislative process adopted by it ' n making other
law,. In the premises, an amendment "Of the Constitution can be nothing
but "law".
A comparative study of other Constitutions
indicates that no particular pattern is followed. AR the Constitutions confer
an ,express power to amend, most of them provide for legislative procedure with
special majority, referendum, convention, etc., and a few with simple majority.
Indeed, Parliament of England, which is a supreme body, can amend the
constitution like any other :statute. As none of the Constitutions contains
provisions similar to Art. 368 and Art. 13(2), neither the said Constitutions
nor the decisions given by courts thereon would be of any assistance in
construing the scope of Art. 368 of our Constitution.
A brief survey of the nature of the amending
process adopted by various constitutions will bring out the futility of any
attempt to draw inspiration from the said opinions or decisions on the said
constitutions. The nature of the amending power in different constitutions
generally depends on the nature of the polity created by the constitution,
namely, whether it is federal or unitary constitution or on the fact whether it
is a written or an unwritten constitution or on the circumstances whether it is
a rigid or a flexible constitution. Particularly the difference can be traced
to the "spirit and genius of the nation in which a particular constitution
has its birth". The following articles of the 'Constitution of the
different countries are brought to our notice by one or other of the counsel
that appeared before us. Art. 5 of the Constitution of the United States of
America, Arts. 125 and 128 of the Commonwealth of Australia Constitution Act,
Art. 92 (1) of the British North American Act, s. 152 of the South African Act,
Art. 217 of the Constitution of, the United States of Brazil, Section 46 of the
Constitution of Ireland, 1937, Arts. 207, 208 and 209 of the Constitution of
the Union of Burma, Art. 88 ,of the Constitution of the Kingdom of Denmark Act,
Art. 90 of 799 the Constitution of the French Republic, 1954, Art. 135 of the
United States of Mexico, Art. 96 of the Constitution of Japan, Art. 112 of the
Constitution of Norway, Art. 85 of the Constitution of the Kingdom of Sweden,
Arts. 118, 119, 120, 121, 122 and 123 of the Constitution of the Swiss
Federation, Arts. 140, 141 and 142 of the Constitution of Venezuela, and Art.
146 of the Constitution of the Union of Soviet Socialist Republics, 1936 and s.
29(4) of Ceylon Constitution Order in Council, 1946.
Broadly speaking amendments can be made by
four methods (i) by ordinary legislative process with or without restrictions,
(ii) by the people through, referendum, (iii) by majority of all the units of a
federal State; and (iv) by a special convention. The first method can be in
four different ways, namely, (i) by the ordinary course of legislation by
absolute majority or by special majority, (See Section 92 (1 )of the British
North America Act, sub-section 152 South African Apt, where under except
sections 35, 137 and 152, other provisions could be amended by ordinary
legislative process by absolute majority. Many constitutions provide for
special majorities.); (ii) by a fixed quorum of members for the consideration
of the proposed amendment and a special majority for its passage; (see the
defunct Constitution of Rumania), (iii) by dissolution and general election on
a particular issue; (see the Constitutions of Belgium, Holland, Denmark and
Norway), and (iv) by a majority of two Houses of Parliament in joint session as
in the Constitution of the South Africa. The second method demands a popular
vote, referendum , or plebiscite as in Switzerland, Australia, Ireland, Italy,
France and Denmark.
The third method is by an agreement in some
form or other of either of the majority or of all the federating units as in
Switzerland, Australia and the United States of America.
The fourth method is generally by creation of
a special body ad hoc for the purpose of constitution revision as in Latin
America. Lastly, some constitutions impose express limitation on the power to
amend. (See Art. 5 of the United States Constitution and the Constitution of
the Fourth French Republic). A more elaborate discussion of this topic may be
found in the American political Constitution by Strong. It will, therefore, be
seen that the power to amend and the procedure to amend radically-differ from
State to State; it is left to the constitution-makers to prescribe the scope of
the power and the method of amendment having regard to the requirements of the
particular State. There is no article in any of the constitutions referred to
us similar to article 13(2) of our Constitution. India adopted a different
system altogether: it empowered the Parliament to amend the Constitution by the
legislative process subject to fundamental rights. The Indian 1 Constitution
has made the amending process comparatively flexible, but it is made subject to
fundamental rights.
800 Now let us consider the argument that the
power to amend is a sovereign power, that the said power is supreme to the
legislative power, that it does not permit any implied limitations and that
amendments made in exercise of that power involve political questions and that,
therefore, they are outside judicial review, This wide proposition is sought to
be supported on the basis of opinions of jurists and judicial decisions. Long
extracts have been read to us from the book "The Amending of the Federal
Constitution (1942)" by Lester Bernhardt Or field, and particular
reference was made to the following passages :
"At the point it may be well to note that
when the Congress is engaged in the amending process it is not legislating. It
is exercising a peculiar power bestowed upon it by Article Five. This Article
for the most part ,controls the process; and other provisions of the
Constitution, such as those relating to the passage of legislation, having but
little bearing." Adverting to the Bill of Rights, the learned author
remarks that they may be repealed just as any other amendment and that they are
no more sacred from a legal standpoint than any other part of the Constitution.
Dealing with the doctrine of implied limitations, he says that it is clearly
untenable. Posing the question 'Is other a law about the amending power of the
Constitution ?", he answers, "there is none". He would even go
to the extent of saying that the sovereignty, if it can be said to exist at
all, is located in the amending body. The author is certainly a strong advocate
of the supremacy of the amending power and an opponent of the doctrine of
implied limitations. His opinion is based upon the terms of Art. 5 of the
Constitution of the United States of America and his interpretation of the
decisions of the Supreme Court of America. Even such an extreme exponent of the
doctrine does not say that a particular constitution cannot expressly impore
restrictions on the power to amend or that a court cannot reconcile the
articles couched in unlimited phraseology. Indeed Art. 5 of the American
Constitution imposes express limitations on the amending power. Some passages
from the book "Political Science and Government" by James Wilford
Garner are cited. Garner points out :
"An unamendable constitution, said
Mulford, is the &&worst tyranny of time, or rather the very tyranny of
time" But he also notices "The provision for amendment should be
neither so rigid as to make needed changes practically impossible nor so
flexible as to encourage frequent and 801 unnecessary changes and thereby lower
the authority of the Constitution." Munro in his book "The Government
of the United States", 5th Edition, uses strong words when he says
"....... it is impossible to conceive of an unamendable constitution as
anything but a contradiction in terms." The learned author says that such
a constitution would constitute "government by the graveyards." Hugh
Evander Wills in his book "Constitutional Law of the United States"
avers that the doctrine of amendability of the Constitution is grounded in the
doctrine of the sovereignty of the people and that it has no such implied
limitations as that an amendment shall not contain a new grant of power or
change the dual form of government or change the protection of the Bill of
Rights, or make any other change in the Constitution. Herman Finer in his book
"The Theory and Practice of Modem Government" defines "constitution"
as its process of amendment, for, in his view, to amend is to deconstitute and
reconstitute. The learned author concludes that the amending clause is so
fundamental to a constitution that he is tempted to call it the constitution
itself. But the learned author recognizes that difficulty in amendment
certainly products circumstances and makes impossible the surreptitious
abrogation of rights guaranteed in the constitution. William S. Livingston in
"Federalism and Constitutional Change" says :
"The formal procedure of amendment is of
greater importance than the informal processes, because it constitutes a higher
authority to which appeal lies on any question that may arise." But there
are equally eminent authors who express a different view. In "American Jurisprudence",
2nd Edition, Vol. 16, it is stated that a statute and a constitution though of
unequal dignity are both laws. Another calls the constitution of a State as one
of the laws of the State.
Cooley in his book on "Constitutional
Law" opines that changes in the fundamental laws of the State must be
indicated by the people themselves. He further implies limitations to the
amending power from the belief in the constitution itself, such as, the
republican form of Government cannot be abolished as it would be revolutionary
in ifs characters. In the same book it is further said that the power to amend
the constitution by legislative action does not confer the power to break it
any more than it confers the power to legislate on any other subject contrary to
the prohibitions. C. F. Strong in his book "Modem Polical
Constitutions", 1963 edition, does not accept the theory of absolute
sovereignty of the amending power which does not brook any limitations, for he
says.
802 "In short, it attempts to arrange
for the recreation of a constituent assembly whenever such matters are in
future to be considered, even though that assembly be nothing more than the
ordinary legislature acting under certain restrictions. At the same time, there
may be some elements of the constitution which the constituent assembly wants
to remain unalterable by the action of any authority whatsoever. These elements
are to be distinguished from the rest, and generally come under the heading of
fundamental law.
Thus, for example, the American Constitution,
the oldest of the existing Constitutions, asserts that by no process of
amendment shall any State, without its own consent, be deprived of its equal
suffrage in the Senate, , while among the Constitutions more recently
promulgated, those of the Republics of; France and Italy, each containing a
clause stating that the republican form of government cannot be the subject of
an amending proposals" it is not necessary to multiply citations from
text-books.
A catena of American decisions have been
cited before us in support of the contention that the unending power is a
supreme power or that it involves political issues which are not justiciable.
It would be futile to consider them. at length, for after going through them
carefully we find that there are no considered judgments of the American
Courts, which would have a persuasive effect in that regard. In the
Constitution of the United States of America, prepared by Edwards S. Corwin,
Legislative Reference Service, Library of Congress, (1953 edn.), the following
summary under the heading "Judicial Review under Article V" is given
:
"Prior to 1939, the Supreme Court had
taken cognizance of a number of diverse objections to the validity of specific
amendments. Apart from holding that official notice of ratification by the
several States was conclusive upon the Courts, it had treated these questions
as justiciable, although it had uniformly rejected them on the merits. In that
year, however, the whole subject was thrown into confusion by the inconclusive
decision in Coleman v. Miller. This case came up on a writ of certiorari to the
Supreme Court of Kansas to review the denial of a writ of mandamus to compel
the Secretary of the Kansas Senate to erase an endorsement on a resolution
ratifying the child labour amendment to the Constitution to re-effect that it
had been adopted by the Kansas Senate. The attempted ratification was 803
assailed on three grounds : (1) that the amendment had been previously rejected
by the State Legislature; (2) that it was no longer open to ratification
because an unreasonable period of time thirteen years, had elapsed since its
submission to the States, and (3) that the lieutenant governor had no right to
cast the deciding vote in the Senate in favour of ratification. Four opinions
were written in the Supreme Court, no one of which commanded the support of
more than four members of the Court. The majority ruled that the plain-tiffs,
members of the Kansas State Senate, had a sufficient interest in the
controversy to give the federal courts jurisdiction to review the case. Without
agreement as to the grounds for their decision, a different majority affirmed
the judgment of the Kansas court denying the relief sought. Four members who
concur-red in the result had voted to dismiss the writ on the ground that the
amending process "is political" in its. entirety, from submission
until an amendment becomes part of the Constitution, and is not subject to
judicial guidance, control or interference at any point." whether the
contention that the lieutenant governor should have been permitted to cast the
deciding vote in favour of ratification presented a justiciable controversy was
left undecided, the court being equally divided on the point. In an opinion
reported as "the opinion of the Court"' but in which it appears that
only three Justices concurred, Chief Justice Hughes declared that the writ of'
mandamus was properly denied because the question as to the effect of the
previous rejection of the amendment and the lapse of time since it was
submitted to the States were political questions which should be left to
Congress.
On the same day, the Court dismissed a. writ
of certiorari to review a decision 'of the Kentucky Court of Appeals declaring
the action of the Kentucky General Assembly purporting to ratifying the child
labour amendment illegal and void. Inasmuch as the governor had forwarded the
certified copy of the resolution to the Secretary of State before being served
with a copy of the restraining order issued by the State Court, the Supreme
Court found that there 'was no longer a controversy susceptible of judicial
determination." This passage, in our view, correctly summarises the
American law on the subject. It will be clear there from that prior to 1939 the
Supreme Court of America had treated the objections to the validity of specific
amendments as justiciable and that only in 1939 it rejected them in an
inconclusive judgment without 804 discussion. In this state of affairs we
cannot usefully draw much from the judicial wisdom of the Judges of the Supreme
Court of America.
One need not cavil at the description of an
amending power as sovereign power, for it is sovereign only within the scope of
the power conferred by a particular constitution.
All the authors also agree, that a particular
constitution can expressly limit the power of amendment, both substantive and
procedural. The only conflict lies in the fact that some authors do not pen-nit
implied limitations when the power of amendment is expressed in general words.
But others countenance such limitations by construction or otherwise. But none
of the authors goes to the extent of saying, which is the problem before us,
that when there are conflicting articles couched in widest terms, the court has
no jurisdiction to construe and harmonize them. If some of the authors meant to
say that-in our view, they did not-we cannot agree with them, for, in that
event this Court would not be discharging its duty.
Nor can we appreciate the arguments repeated
before us by learned counsel for the respondents that the amending process
involves political questions which are, outside the scope of judicial review.
When a matter comes before the Court, its jurisdiction does not depend upon the
nature of the question raised but on die, question whether the said matter is
expressly or by necesssary implication excluded from its jurisdiction.
Secondly, it is not possible to define what is a political question and what is
not. The character of a question depends upon the circumstances and the nature
of a political society. To put if differently, the court does not decide any
political question at all in the ordinary sense of the. term, but only
ascertains whether Parliament is acting within the scope of the amending power.
It may be that Parliament seeks to amend the
Constitution for political reasons, but the Court in denying that power will
not be deciding on political questions, but will only be holding that
Parliament has no power to amend particular articles of the Constitution for
any purpose whatsoever, be it political or otherwise. We, therefore, hold that
there is nothing in the nature of the amending power which enables Parliament
to override all the express or implied limitations imposed on that power. As we
have pointed out earlier, our Constitution adopted a novel method in the sense
that Parliament makes the amendment by legislative process subject to certain
restrictions and,that the amendment so made being law" is.subject to Art.
13(2).
The next argument is based upon the
expression "amendment" in Art. 368 of the Constitution and if is
contended that the said 805 expression has-.a Positive and a negative content
and that in exercise of the power amendment parliament cannot destroy the
structure of the Constitution, but it can only modify the provisions thereof
within the framework of the original instrument for its better effectuation. If
the fundamentals would be amenable to the ordinary process of amendment with a
special majority, the argument proceeds, the institutions of the President can
be abolished, the parliamentary executive can be removed, the fundamental
rights can be abrogated, the concept of federalism' can be obliterated and in
short the sovereign democratic republic can be converted into a totalitarian
system of government. There is considerable force in this argument. Learned and
lengthy arguments are advanced to sustain it or to reject it. But we are
relieved of the necessity to express our opinion on this all important question
as, so far as the fundamental rights are concerned, the question raised can be
answered on a narrower basis. This question may arise for consideration only if
Parliament seeks to destroy the structure of the Constitution embodied in the
provisions other than in Part III of the Constitution. We do not, therefore,
propose to express our opinion in that regard.
In the view we have taken on the scope of
Art. 368 vis--a vis the fundamental rights, it is also unnecessary to express
our opinion on the question whether the amendment of the fundamental rights is
covered by the proviso to Art.
368.
The result is that the Constitution
(Seventeenth Amendment) Act, 1964, inasmuch as it takes away or abridges the
fundamental rights is void under Art. 13(2) of the Constitution.
The next question is whether our decision
should be given retrospective operation. During the period between 1950 and
1967 i.e 17 years as many as 20 amendments were made in our Constitution. But
in the context of the present petitions it would be enough if we notice the
amendments affecting fundamental right to property. The Constitution came into
force on January 26, 1950. The Constitution (First Amendment) Act, 1951,
amended Arts. 15 and 19, and Arts. 31A and 31-B were inserted with
retrospective effect. The object of the amendment was said to be to validate
the acquisition of zamindaries or the abolition of permanent settlement without
interference from courts. The occasion for the amendment was that the High
Court of Patna in Kameshwar Singh v, State of Bihar(1) held that the Bihar Land
Reforms Act (30 of 1950) passed by the State of Bihar was unconstitutional,
while the High Courts of Allahabad and Nagpur upheld the validity of
corresponding legislations in Uttar Pradesh and Madhya Pradesh respectively.
(1) A. I. R. 1951 Patna 91.
p.C.T.167-6 806 The amendment was made when
the appeals from those decisions were pending in the Supreme Court. In Sankari
Prasad's case(1) the constitutionality of the said amendment was questioned but
the amendment was upheld. It may be noticed that the said amendment was not
made on the basis of the power to amend fundamental rights recognized by this
Court but only in view of the conflicting decisions of High Courts and without
waiting for the final decision from this Court.
article 31-A was again amended by the
Constitution (Fourth Amendment) Act, 1955. Under that amendment cl. (2) of Art.
31 was amended and cl. (2-A) was inserted
therein. While in the original article 31-A the general expression "any
provisions of his Part" was found, in the amended article the scope was
restricted only.to the violation of Arts. 14, 19 and 31 and 4 other clauses
were included, namely, clauses providing for (a) taking over the management of
any property by the State for a limited-period; (b) amalgamation of two or more
corporations; (c) extinguishment or modification of rights of person;
interested in corporations; and (d) extinguishment or modification of rights
accruing under any agreement, lease or licence relating to minerals, and the
definition of "estate" was enlarged in order to include the interests
of raiyats and under-raiyats. The expressed object of the amendment was to
carry out important social welfare legislations on the desired lines, to
improve the national economy of the State and to avoid serious difficulties
raised by courts in that regard. Article 31A has further been amended by the
Constitution (Fourth Amendment) Act, 1955. By the said amendment in the Ninth
Schedule to the Constitution entries 14 to 20 were added.
The main objects of this amending Act was to
distinguish the power of compulsory acquisition or requisitioning of private
property and the deprivation of property and to extend the scope of Art. 31-A
to cover different categories of social welfare legislations and to enable
monopolies in particular trade or business to be created in favour of the
State.
Amended Art. 31(2)makes the adequacy of
compensation not justiciable. It may be said-that the Constitution (Fourth
Amendment) Act, 1955 was made by Parliament as this Court recognized the power
of Parliament to amend Part III of the Constitution; but it can' also be said
with some plausibility that, as Parliament had exercised the power even before
the. decision of this Court in Sankari Prasad's case(1), it would have amended
the Constitution even if the said decision was not given by this Court. The
Seventeenth Amendment Act was made on June 20, 1964. The occasion for this
amendment was the decision of this Court in Karimbil Kunhikoman v. State of
Kerala(2), which struck down the Kerala Agrarian Relations Act IV of 1961
relating to ryotwari lands. Under that amendment the definition of the
expression "estate" was enlarged so as to take (1) [1952] S.C.R. 89,
105 (2) [1962] Supp. 1 S.C.R. 829 807 in any land held under ryotwari
settlement and any held or let for purposes of agriculture or for purposes
ancillary thereto, including waste land, forest land, land for pasture or sites
of buildings and other structures occupied by cultivators of land, agricultural
labourers and village artisans. In the Ninth Schedule the amendment included
items 21 to 65. In the objects and reasons it was stated that the
definition"'estate" was not wide enough, that the courts had struck
down many land reform Acts and that, therefore, in order to give them protection
the amendment was made. The validity of the Seventeenth Amendment Act was
questioned in this Court and was held to be valid in Sajian Singh's case(1).
From the history of these amendments, two things appear, namely,
unconstitutional laws were made and they were protected by the amendment of the
Constitution or the amendments were made in order to protect the future laws
which would be void but for the amendments. But the fact remains that this
Court held as early as in 1951 that Parliament had power to amend the
fundamental rights. It may, therefore, said that the Constitution (Fourth
Amendment) Act, 1955, and the Constitution (Seventeenth Amendment) Act, 1964,
were based upon the scope of the power to end recognized by this Court. Further
the Seventeenth Amendment Act was also approved by this Court.
Between 1950 and 1967 the Legislatures of
various States made laws bringing about an agrarian revolution in our country
zamindaries, inams and other intermediary estates were abolished, vested rights
were created in tenants, consolidation of holdings of villages was made,
ceilings were fixed and the surplus lands transferred to tenants.
All these were done on the, basis of the
correctness of the decisions in Sankari Prasads case(2) and Sajjan Singh's
case(1), namely, that Parliament had the power to amend the fundamental rights
and that Acts in regard to estates were outside judicial scrutiny on the ground
they infringed the said rights. The agrarian structure of our country has been
revolutionised on the basis of the said laws. Should we now give
retrospectivity to our decision, it would introduce chaos and unsettle the
conditions in our country. Should we hold that because of the said consequences
Parliament had power to take away fundamental rights, a time might come when we
would gradually and imperceptibly pass under a totalitarian rate. Learned
counsel for the petitioners as well as those for the respondents placed us on
the horns of this dilemma, for they have taken extreme positions-leamed counsel
for the petitioners want us to reach the logical position by holding that all
the said laws are void and the learned counsel for the respondents persuade us
to hold that Parliament has unlimited power and, if it chooses, it can do away
with fundamental rights. We do not think that (1) [1965] 1 S.C.R. 933.
(2) [1952] S.C.R. 89, 808 this Court is so
helpless. As the highest Court in the land we must evolve some reasonable
principle to meet this extraordinary situation. There is an essential
distinction between Constitution and statutes. Comparatively speaking,
Constitution is permanent; it is an organic statute; it grows by its own
inherent force. The constitutional concepts are couched in elastic terms.
Courts are expected to and indeed should interpret, its terms without doing
violence to the language, to suit the expanding needs of the society. In this
process and in a real sense they make laws. Though it is not admitted, the said
role of this Court is effective and cannot be ignored. Even in the realm of ordinary
statutes, the subtle working of the process is apparent though the approach is
more conservative and inhibitive.--In the constitutional field, therefore, to
meet the present extraordinary situation that may be caused by our decision, we
must evolve some doctrine which has roots in reason and precedents so that the
past may be preserved and the future protected.
There are two doctrines familiar to American
Jurisprudence, one is described as Blackstonian theory and the other as
"prospective over-ruling", which may have some relevance to the
present enquiry. Blackstone in his Commentaries, 69 (15th edn., 1809) stated
the common law rule that the duty of the Court was "not to pronounce a new
rule but to maintain and expound .the old one". It means the Judge does
not make law but only discovers or finds the true law. The law has always been
the same. If a subsequent decision changes the earlier one, the latter decision
does not make law but only discovers the correct principle of law. The result
of this view is that it is necessarily retrospective ,operation. But Jurists,
George F. Canfield, Robert Hill Freeman, John Henry Wigmore and Cardozo, have
expounded the doctrine of "prospective over-ruling" and suggested it
as "a useful judicial .tool". In the words of Canfield the said
expression means "......a court should recognize a duty to announce a new
and better rule for future transactions whenever the court has reached the
conviction that an old rule (as established by the precedents) is unsound even
though feeling compelled by stare decisis to apply the old and condemned rule
to the instant case and to transactions which had already taken place."
Cardozo, before he became a Judge of the Supreme Court of the United States of
America, when he was the Chief Justice of New York State addressing the Bar
Association said thus The rule (the Blackstonian rule) that we are asked to
apply is out of tune with the life about us. It has been made discordant by the
forces that generate a 809 living law. We apply it to this case because the
repeal might work hardship to those who have trusted to its existence. We give
notice however that any one trusting to it hereafter will do at his
peril." The Supreme Court of the United States of America, in the year
1932, after Cardozo became an Associate Justice of that Court in Great Northern
Railway v. Sunburst Oil & Ref.
Co.,(1) applied the said doctrine to the
facts of that case.
In that case the Montana Court had adhered to
its previous construction of the statute in question but had announced that
that interpretation would not be followed in the future. It was contended
before the Supreme Court of the United States of America that a decision of a
court overruling earlier decision and not giving its ruling retroactive
operation violated the due process clause of the 14th Amendment. Rejecting that
plea, Cardozo said :
"This is not a case where a Court in
overruling an earlier decision has come to the new ruling of retroactive
dealing and thereby has made invalid what was followed in the doing. Even that
may often be done though litigants not infrequently have argued to the contrary
.... This is a case where a Court has refused to make its ruling retroactive,
and the novel stand is taken that the Constitution of the United States is
infringed by the refusal. We think that the Federal Constitution has no voice
upon the subject. A state in defining the elements of adherence to precedent
may make a choice for itself between the principle of forward operation and
that of relation backward. It may be so that the decision of the highest
courts, though later over-ruled, was law nonetheless for intermediate
transactions .... On the other hand, it may hold to the ancient dogma that the
law declared by its Courts had a platonic or ideal existence before the act of
declaration, in which event, the discredited declaration will be viewed as if
it had never been and to reconsider declaration as law from the beginning... .
The choice for any state maybe determined by the juristic philosophy of the
Judges of her Courts, their considerations of law, its origin and nature."
The opinion of Cardozo tried to harmonize the doctrine of prospective
over-ruling with that of stare decisis.
In 1940, Hughes, C.J., in Chicot County
Drainage District v.
Baxter State Bank(2) stated thus (1) (1932)
287 U.S. 358, 366. 17 L. Ed. 360.
(2) (1940) 308 U.S. 371.
810 "The law prior to the determination
of unconstitutionality is an operative fact and may have consequences which
cannot justly be ignored. The past cannot always be erased by a new judicial
declaration." In Griffin v. Illionis(1) the Supreme Court of America
reaffirmed the doctrine laid down in Sunburst's case (2).
There, a statute required defendants to
Submit bills of exceptions as a pre-requisite to an appeal from a conviction;
the Act was held unconstitutional in that it provided no means whereby indigent
defendants could secure a copy of the record for this purpose. Frankfurter, J.,
in that context observed "...... in arriving at a new principle, the judicial
process is not important to, define its scope and limits. Adjudication is not a
mechanical exercise nor does it compel 'either/or' determination." In Wolf
v. Colorado(3) a majority of the Supreme Court held that in a prosecution in a
State Court for a state crime, the 14th Amendment did not forbid the admission
of evidence obtained by an unreasonable search and seizure. But in Mapp. v.
Ohio(4) the Supreme Court reversed that decision and held that all evidence
obtained by searches and seizure in violation of the 4th Amendment of the
Federal Constitution was, by virtue of the due process clause of the 14th
Amendment guaranteeing the right to privacy free from unreasonable State
instrusion, inadmissible in a State court. In Linkletter v. Walker(5) the question
arose whether the exclusion of the rule enunciated in Mapp v.
Ohio(4) did not apply to State Court
convictions which had become final before the date of that judgment. Mr.
Justice Clarke, speaking for the majority observed "We believe that the existence
of the Wolf doctrine prior to Mapp is 'an operative' fact and may have
consequences which cannot justly be ignored. The past cannot always be erased
by a new judicial declaration." "Mapp had as its prima purpose the
enforcement of the Fourth Amendment through the inclusion of the exclusionary
rule within its rights..............
We cannot say that this purpose would be
advanced by making the rule retrospective.
The misconduct of the police prior to Mapp
has already occurred and win (1) [1956]351U.S.12,2..(2) (1932) 287 U. S.
358,366: 77 L Ed. 360.
(3) [1948-49] 338 U. S. 25: 193L.Ed. 872. (4)
[1966] 367 U.S. 643: 6 L. Ed.
(5) [1965] 381 U.S. 618.(2nd Edn.) 1081.
811 not be corrected by releasing the
prisoners involved.... On the other hand, the States relied on Wolf and
followed its command.
Final judgments of conviction were entered
prior to Mapp. Again and again the Court refused to reconsider Wolf and gave
its implicit approval to hundreds of cases in their application of its rule. In
rejecting the Wolf doctrine as to, the exclusionary rule the purpose was to
deter the lawless action of the police add to effectively enforce the Fourth
Amendment. That purpose will not at this late date be served by the wholesale
release of the guilty victims." "Finally, there are interests in the,
administration of justice and the integrity of the judicial process to
consider. To make the rule of Mapp retrospective would tax the administration
of justice to the utmost.
Hearings would have to be held on the excludability
of evidence long since destroyed, misplaced or deteriorated. If it is excluded,
the witness available at the time of the original trial will not be available
or if located their memory will be dimmed. To thus legitimate such an
extraordinary procedural weapon that has no bearing on guilt would seriously
disrupt the administration of justice." This case has reaffirmed the
doctrine of prospective overruling and has taken a pragmatic approach in
refusing to give it retroactivity. In short, in America the doctrine of
prospective overruling is now accepted in all branches of law, including
constitutional law. But the carving of the limits of retrospectivity of the new
rule is left to courts to be done, having regard to the requirements of
justice.
Even in England the Blackstonian theory was
criticized by Bentham and Austin. In Austin's Jurisprudence, 4th Ed., at page
65, the learned author says :
"What hindered Blackstone was 'the
childish fiction' employed by our judges, that the judiciary or common law is
not 'Made by them, butis a miraculous something made, by nobody, existing, I
suppose, from eternity, and merely declared from time to time by the
Judges." Though English Courts in the past accepted the Blackstonian
theory and though the House of Lords strictly adhered to the doctrine of
'precedent' in the earlier years, both the doctrines were practically given up
by the "Practice Statement (Judicial Precedent)" issued by the House
of Lords recorded in (1966) 1 W.L.R. 1234. Lord Gardiner L.C., speaking for the
House of Lords made the following observations 812 "Their Lordships
nevertheless recognise that too rigid adherence to precedent may lead to
injustice in a particular case and also unduly restrict the proper development
of the law.
They propose, therefore, to modify their
present practice and, while treating former decisions of this House as normally
binding, to depart from a previous decision when it appears right to do so.
In this connection they will bear in mind the
danger of disturbing retrospectively the basis on which contracts, settlements
of property and fiscal arrangements have been entered into and also the
especial need for certainty as to the criminal law." This announcement is
not intended to affect the use of precedent elsewhere than in this House."
It will be seen from this passage that the House of Lords hereafter in
appropriate cases may depart from its previous decision when it appears right
to do so and in so departing will bear in mind the danger of giving effect to the
said decision retroactivity. We consider that what the House of Lords means by
this statement is that in differing from the precedents it will do so only
without interefering with the transactions that had taken place on the basis of
earlier decisions. This decision, to a large extent, modifies the Blackstonian
theory and accepts, though not expressly but by necessary implication the
doctrine of "prospective overruling." Let us now consider some of the
objections to this doctrine.
The objections are: (1) the doctrine involved
legislation by courts; (2) it would not encourage parties to prefer appeals as
they would not get any benefit therefrom; (3) the declaration for the future
would only be obiter, (4) it is not a desirable change; and (5) the doctrine of
retroactivity serves as a brake on court which otherwise might be tempted to be
so fascile in overruling. But in our view, these objections are not
insurmountable. If a court can over-rule its earlier decision-there cannot be
any dispute now that the court can do so there cannot be any valid reason why
it should not restrict its ruling to the future and not to the past. Even if
the party filing an appeal may not be benefited by it, in similar appeals which
he may file after the change in the law he will have the benefit. The decision
cannot be obiter for what the court in effect does is to declare the law but on
the basis of another doctrine restricts its scope. Stability in law does not
mean that injustice shall be perpetuated. An illuminating article on the
subject is found in Pennsylvania Law Review, [Vol. I 10 p. 650].
813 It is a modem doctrine suitable for a
fast moving society.
It does not do away with the doctrine of
stare decisis, but confines it to past transactions. It is true that in one
sense the court only declares the law, either customary or statutory or
personal law. While in strict theory it may be said that the doctrine involves
making of law, what the court really does is to declare the law but refuses to
give retroactivity to it. It is really a pragmatic solution reconciling the two
conflicting doctrines, namely, that a court finds law and that it does make
law. It finds law but restricts its operation to the future. It enables the
court to bring about a smooth transition by correcting its errors without
disturbing the impact of those errors on the past transactions. It is left to
the discretion of the court to prescribe the limits of the retroactivity and
thereby it enables it to would the relief to meet the ends of justice.
In India there is no statutory prohibition
against the court refusing to give retroactivity to the law declared by it.
Indeed,. the doctrine of res judicata
precludes any scope for retroactivity in respect of a subject-matter that has
been finally decided between the parties. Further, Indian court by
interpretation reject retroactivity. to statutory provisions though couched in
general terms on the ground that they affect vested rights. The present case
only attempts a further extension of the said rule against retroactivity.
Our Constitution does not expressly or by
necessary implication speak against the doctrine of prospective over-ruling.
Indeed, Arts. 32, 141 and 142 are couched in
such wide and elastic terms as to enable this Court to formulate legal doctrines
to meet the ends of justice. The only limitation thereon is reason, restraint
and injustice. Under Art. 32, for the enforcement of the fundamental rights the
Supreme Court has the power to issue suitable directions or orders or writs.
Article 141 says that the law declared by the Supreme Court shall be binding on
all courts; and Art. 142 enables it in the exercise of its jurisdiction to pass
such decree or make such order as is necessary for doing complete justice in
any cause or matter pending before it. These articles are designedly made
comprehensive to enable the Supreme Court to declare law and to give such
directions or pass such orders as are necessary to do complete justice.
The expression "declared" is wider
than the words "found or made". To declare is to announce opinion.
Indeed, the latter involves the process, while the former expresses result.
Interpretation, ascertainment and evolution are parts of the process, while
that interpreted, ascertained or evolved is declared as law. The law declared
by the Supreme Court is the law of the and. If so, we do not see any acceptable
reason why it, in declaring the law in superses814 sion of the law declared by
it earlier, could not restrict the operation of the law as declared to future
and save the transactions, whether statutory or otherwise that were effected on
the basis of the earlier law. To deny this power to the Supreme Court on the
basis of some outmoded theory that the Court only finds law but does not make
it is to make ineffective the powerful instrument of. justice placed in the
hands of the highest judiciary of this country.
As this Court for the first time has been
called upon to apply the doctrine evolved in a different country under
different ,circumstances, we would like to move warily in the beginning. We
would lay down the following propositions : (I) The doctrine of prospective
over-ruling, can be invoked only in matters arising under our Constitution; (2
it an be applied only by the highest court of the country, i.e., the Supreme Court
as it has the constitutional jurisdiction to declare an binding on all the
courts in India; (3) the scope of the retroactive operation of the law declared
by the Supreme Court superseding its earlier decisions .is left to its
discretion to be moulded in accordance with the justice of the cause or matter
before it.
We have arrived at two conclusions, namely,
(1) Parliament has no power to amend Part III of the Constitution so as to take
away or abridge the fundamental rights; and (2) this is a fit case to invoke
and apply the doctrine or prospective overruling. What then is the effect of
our conclusion on the instant case ?. Having regard to the history of the
amendments their impact on the social and economic affairs of our country and
the chaotic situation that may be brought about by the sudden withdrawal at
this stage of the amendments from the Constitution, we think that considerable
judicial restraint is called for. We, therefore, declare that our decision will
not affect the validity of the Constitution (Seventeenth Amendment) Act, 1964,
or other amendments made to the Constitution taking away or abridging the
fundamental rights. We further declare that in future Parliament will have no
power to amend Part III of the Constitution so as to take away or abridge the
fundamental rights. In this case we do not propose to express our opinion on
the question of the scope of the amendability of the provisions of the
Constitution other than the fundamental rights, as it does not arise for
consideration before us. Nor are we called upon to express out opinion on the
question regarding the scope of the amends ability of Part Ill of the
constitution otherwise than by taking away or abridging the fundamental rights.
We will not also indicate our view one way or other whether any of the Acts
questioned can be sustained under the provisions of the Constitution without
the aid of Arts. 31A, 31B and the 9th Schedule.
815 The aforesaid discussion leads to the
following results (1) The power of the Parliament to amend the Constitution is
derived from Arts. 245, 246 and 248 of the Constitution and not from Art.
368 thereof which only deals with procedure.
Amendment is a legislative process.
(2) Amendment is 'law' within the meaning of
Art. 13 of the Constitution and, therefore, if it takes away or abridges the
rights conferred by Part III thereof, it is void.
(3) The Constitution (First Amendment) Act,
1951, Constitution (Fourth Amendment) Act, 1955, and,the Constitution
(Seventeenth Amendment) Act, 1964, abridge the scope. of the fundamental
rights. But, on the basis of earlier decisions of this Court, they were valid.
(4) On the application of the doctrine of
'prospective over-ruling', as explained by us earlier, our decision will have
only prospective operation and, therefore, the said amendments will continue to
be valid.
(5) We declare that the Parliament will have
no power from the date of this decision to amend any of the provisions of Part
III of the Constitution so as to take away or abridge the fundamental rights
enshrined therein.
(6) As the Constitution (Seventeenth
Amendment) Act holds the field, the validity of the two impugned Acts, namely,
the Punjab Security of Land Tenures Act X of 1953, and the Mysore Land Reforms
Act X of 1962, as amended by Act XIV of 1965, cannot be questioned on the
ground that they offend Arts. 13, 14 or 31 of the Constitution.
Before we close, it would be necessary to
advert to an argument advanced on emotional plane. It was said that if the
provisions of the Constitution could not be amended it would lead to
revolution. We have not said that the provisions of the Constitution cannot be
amended but what we have said is that they cannot be amended so as to take away
or abridge the fundamental rights. Nor can we appreciate the argument that all
the agrarian reforms which the Parliament in power wants to effectuate cannot
be brought about without amending the fundamental rights. It was exactly to
prevent this attitudeand to project the rights of the that the fundamental
rights were inserted in the Constitution. If it is the duty of the Parliament
to enforce the directive principles, it is equally its duty to enforce them
without infringing the fundamental rights. The Constitution-makers thought that
it could be done and we also think that the directive prin816 ciples can
reasonably be enforced within the self-regulatory machinery provided by Part
III. Indeed both Parts III and IV of the Constitution form an integrated scheme
and is elastic enough to respond to the changing needs of the society. The
verdict of the Parliament on the scope of the law of social control of
fundamental rights is not final, but justiciable. If not so, the whole scheme
of the Constitution will break. What we canI not understand is how the
enforcement of the provisions of the Constitution can bring about a revolution.
History shows that revolutions are brought about not by the majorities but by
the minorities and some time by military coups. The existence of an all
comprehensive amending power cannot prevent revolutions, if there is chaos in
the country brought about by mis-rule or abuse of power. On the other hand,
such a restrictive power gives stability to the country and prevents it from
passing under a totalitarian or dictatorial regime. We cannot obviously base
our decision on such hypothetical or extraordinary situations which may be
brought about with or without amendments. Indeed, a Constitution is only
permanent and not eternal. There is nothing to choose between destruction by
amendment or by revolution, the former is brought about by totalitarian rule,
which cannot brook constitutional checks and the other by the discontentment
brought about by mis-rule. If either happens, the constitution will be a scrap
of paper. Such considerations are out of place in construing the provisions of
the Constitution by a court of law.
Nor are we impressed by the argument that if
the, power of amendment is 'not all comprehensive there will be no way to
change the structure of our Constitution or abridge the fundamental rights even
if the whole country demands for such a change. Firstly, this visualizes an
extremely unforeseeable and extravagant demand; but even if such a contingency
arises the residuary power of the Parliament may be relied upon to call for a Constituent
Assembly for making a new Constitution or radically changing it. The recent Act
providing for a poll in Goa, Daman and Diu is an instance of analogous exercise
of such residuary power by the Parliament. We do not express our final opinion
on this important question.
A final appeal is made to us that we shall
not take a different view as the decision in Sankari Prasad's case(1) held the
field for many years. While ordinarily this Court will be reluctant to reverse
its previous decision, it is its duty in the constitutional field to correct
itself as early as possible, for otherwise the future progress of the country
and the happiness of the people will be at stake.
As we are convinced that the decision in
Sankari Prasad's case(1) is wrong, it is pre-eminently a typical case where
this Court should over-rule it. The longer it holds the field the greater will
(1) [1952] S.C.R 89, 105 817 be the scope for erosion of fundamental rights. As
it contains the seeds of destruction of the cherished rights of the people the
sooner it is over-ruled the better for the country.
This argument is answered by the remarks made
by this Court in the recent judgment in The Superintendent and Legal
Remembrancer State of West Bengal v., The Corporation of Calcutta(1).
"The third contention need not detain us
]'or it has been rejected by this Court in The Bengal Immunity Company Limited
v. The State of Bihar(2) . There a Bench of 7 Judges unanimously held that
there was nothing in the Constitution that prevented the Supreme Court from
departing from a previous decision of its own if it was satisfied of its error
and of its baneful effect on the general interest of the public. If the
aforesaid rule of construction accepted by this Court is inconsistent with the
legal philosophy of our Constitution, it is our duty to correct ourselves and
lay down the right rule. In constitutional matters which affect the evolution
of our polity, we must more readily do so than in other branches of law, as
perpetuation of a mistake will be harmful to public interests. While continuity
and consistency are conducive to the smooth evolution of the rule of law,
hesitancy to set right deviation will retard its growth. In this case, as we
are satisfied that the said rule of construction is inconsistent with our
republican polity and, if accepted, bristles with anomalies, we have no
hesitation to reconsider our earlier decision." In the result the
petitions are dismissed, but in the circumstances without costs.
Wanchoo, J. This Special Bench of eleven
Judges of this Court has been constituted to consider the correctness of the
decision of this Court in Sri Sankari Prasad Singh Deo v. Union of India(,,)
which was accepted as correct by the majority in Sajjan Singh v. State of
Rajasthan (4) .
The reference has been made in three
petitions challenging the constitutionality of the Seventeenth Amendment to the
Constitution. In one of the petitions, the inclusion, of the Punjab Security of
Land Tenures Act, (No. X of 1953) in the Ninth Schedule, which makes it immune
from. attack under any provisions contained in Part III of the Constitution'
has been attacked on the ground that the Seventeenth Amendment is in itself
unconstitutional. In the other two petitions, the inclusion of the Mysore Land
Reforms Act, (No. 10 of 1962) has been attacked on the same grounds. It is not
necessary to set out the facts in (1) [1967] 2 S.C.R. 170,176 (2) [1955]
2S.C.R.603.
(3) [1952] S.C.R. 89.
(4) [1965] 1.C.S.R. 933.
818 the three petitions for present purposes.
The main argument in all the three petitions has been as to the scope and
effect of Art. 368 of the Constitution and the power conferred thereby to amend
the Constitution.
Before we come to the specific I points
raised in the present petitions, we may indicate the circumstances in which
Sankari Prasad's case(1) as well as Sajjan Singh's case (2) came to be decided
and what they actually decided.
The Constitution came into force on January
26,.1950. It provides in Part III for certain fundamental rights.
Article 31 which is in Part 111, as it
originally stood, provided for compulsory acquisition of property. By clause
(1) it provided that "no person shall be deprived of his property save by
authority of law". Clause (2) ;hereof provided that any law authorising taking
of Possession or acquisition of property must provide for compensation therefor
and either fix the amount of compensation or specify the principles on which,
and the manner in which the compensation was to be determined and paid.
Clause(4) made a special provision to the effect that if any Bill pending at
the commencement of the Constitution in the Legislature of a State had, after
it had been passed by such Legislature, been reserved for the consideration of
the President and had received his assent, then such law would not be called in
question though it contravened the provisions of cl. (2) relating to
compensation. Clause (6) provided that any law of the State enacted not more
than eighteen months before the Constitution might be submitted to the
President for his certification, and if so certified, it could not be called in
question on the ground that it contravened the provision of cl. (2) of Art. 31
relating to compensation.
These two clauses of Art. 31 were meant to
safeguard legislation which either had been passed by Provincial or State
legislatures or which was on the anvil of State legislatures for the purpose of
agrarian reforms. One such piece of legislation was the Bihar Land Reforms Act,
which was passed in 1950. That Act received the assent of the President as
required under cl. (6) of Art. 31. It was however challenged before the Patna
High Court and was struck down by that court on the ground that it violated
Art' 14 of the Constitution. Then there was an appeal before this Court, but
while that appeal was pending, the First Amendment to the Constitution was
made.
We may briefly refer to what the First
Amendment provided for. It was the First Amendment which was challenged and was
upheld in Sankari Prasad's case(1). The First Amendment contained a number of
provisions; but it is necessary for present purposes only to refer to those
provisions which made changes in Part III of the Constitution. These changes
related to Arts. 15 (1) [1952] S.C.R. 89.
(2) [1965] 1 S.C.R. 933 819 and 19 and in
addition, provided for insertion of two Articles, numbered 31-A and 31-Bin Part
III Article 31-A provided that no law providing for the acquisition by the
State of any estate or of any rights therein or the extinguishment or
modification of any such rights shall be deemed to be void on the ground that
it was. inconsistent with, or took away or abridged any of the rights conferred
by any provision in part Ill. 'The word "estate" was also defined for
the purpose of Art. 31-A Further Article 31-B.
provided for validation of certain Acts and
Regulations and specified such Acts and Regulations in the Ninth Schedule,
which was for the first time added to the Constitution. The Ninth Schedule then
contained 13 Acts, all relating to estates , passed by various legislatures of
the Provinces or States. It laid down that those Acts and Regulations would not
be deemed to be void or ever to have become void, on the ground that they were
inconsistent with. or took away or abridged any of the rights conferred by any
provision of Part III. It further provided that notwithstanding any judgment,
decree or order of any court or tribunal to the contrary, all such Acts and
Regulations subject to the power of any competent legislature to repeal or
amend them, continue in force.
This amendment, and in particular Arts. 31-A
and 31-B were.
immediately challenged by various writ
petitions in this Court and these came to be decided on October 5, 1951 in
Sankari Prasad's case(1). The attack on the validity of the First Amendment was
made on various grounds; but three main grounds which were. taken were, first 1
, that amendments to the Constitution made under Art. 368 were liable to be
tested under Art. 13(2); secondly that in any case as Arts.
31 A and 31-B insert the Constitution by the
First.
Amendment affected the power of the High
Court under Art.
226 1 and of this Court under Articles 132
and 136; the amendment required ratification under the proviso to Art.
368; and, thirdly that Acts. 31-A and 31 B
were invalid on the ground that they related to matters-covered by the State
List, namely, item 18 of List 11, and could not therefore be passed by
Parliament.This Court rejected all the three contentions. It held that although
."law" would ordinarily include constitutional law, there was a clear
demarcation between ordinary law made in the exercise of legislative power and
constitutional law made in the exercise of constituent power, and in the
context of Art. 13, "law" must be taken to mean rules or regulations
made. in exercise of ordinary legislative power and not amendments to, the
Constitution made in the exercise of constituent power; in consequence Art.
13(2) did not affect amendments made under Art. 3 68. It further held that
Arts. 3 1 A and 31-B did not curtail the power of the High Court under Art. 226
or of this court under Arts. 132 and 136and did not require ratification under
the (1) [1952] S.C.R. 89 820 proviso contained in Art. 368. Finally, it was
held thatArts. 31.-A and 31-B were essentially amendments to the Constitution
and Parliament as such had the power to enact such amendments. In consequence,
the First Amendment to the Constitution was upheld as valid.
After this decision, there followed sixteen
more amendment .to the Constitution till we come to the Seventeenth Amendment,
which was passed on June 20, 1964.
There does not seem to have been challenge to
any amendment up to the Sixteenth Amendment, even though two of them, namely,
the Fourth Amendment and the Sixteenth Amendment,, contained changes in the
provisions of Part III of the Constitution. Further the nature of these
amendments was to add to, or alter or delete various other provisions of the
Constitution contained in Part III thereof On December 5, 1961 came the
decision of this Court by which the Kerala Agrarain Reforms Act (No. 4 of
1961), passed by the Kerala legislature, was struck down, among other grounds,
for the reason that ryotwari lands in South India were not estates within the
meaning of Art. 31-A and therefore acquisition of reyotwari land was not
protected under Art. 31-A of the Constitution : [see Karimbil Kunhikoman v.
State of Kerala(1)]. This decision was followed by the Seventeenth Amendment on
June 20, 1964. By this amendment, changes were made in Art. 31-A of the Constitution
and 44 Acts were included in the Ninth Schedule to give them complete
protection from attack under any provision of Part III of the Constitution.
Practically all these Acts related to land tenures and were concerned with
agrarian reforms. This amendment was challenged before this 'Court in Sajjan
Singh's case(2). The points then urged were that as Art.
226 was likely to be affected by the
Seventeenth Amendment, it required ratification under the proviso to Art. 368
and that the decision in Sankari Prasads case(3) which had negatived this
contention required re-consideration. It was also urged that the Seventeenth
Amendment was legislation with respect to land and Parliament bad no right to
legislate in that behalf, and further that as the Seventeenth Amendment
provided that the Acts put in the Ninth Schedule would be valid in spite of the
decision of the Courts, it was unconstitutional.. This Court by a majority of 3
to 2 upheld the correctness of the decision in Sankari Prasad's case(,,). It
further held unanimously that the Seventeenth Amendment did not require
ratification under the proviso to Art. 368 because of its indirect effect on
Art. 226, and that Parliament in enacting the Amendment was not legislating
with respect to land and that it was open to Parliament to validate legislation
which had been invalid by courts. Finally this Court held by majority (1)
[1962] Supp. 1 S.C.R. 829. (2) [1965] 1 S.C.R. 933.
(3) [1952] S.C.R. 89.
821 that the power conferred by Art. 368
included the power to take away fundamental rights guaranteed by Part HI and
that the power to amend was a very wide power and could not be controlled by
the literal dictionary meaning of the word "amend" and that the word
"law" in Art. 13 (2) did not include an amendment of the Constitution
made in pursuance of Art. 368. The minority however doubted the correctness of
the view taken in Sankari Prasads case(1) to the effect that the word
'law" in Art. 13 (2) did not include amendment to the Constitution made
under Art. 368 and therefore doubted the competence of Parliament to make any
amendment to Part III of the Constitution. One of the learned Judges further
doubted whether making a change in the basic features of the Constitution could
be regarded merely as an amendment or would, in effect, be re-writing a part of
the Constitution, and if so, whether it could' be done under Art. 368. It was
because of this doubt thrown on the correctness of the view taken in Sankari
Prasad's case(1) that the present reference has been made to this Special
Bench.
As the question referred to this Bench is of
great constitutional importance and affected legislation passed by various
States, notice was issued to the Advocates General of all States and they have
appeared and, intervened before us. Further a number of persons who were also
affected by the Seventeenth Amendment have been permitted to intervene.
The arguments on behalf of the petitioners
and the interveners who support them may now. be briefly summarised.
It is urged that Art. 368-when it provides
for the amendment of the Constitution merely' contains the procedure for doing
so and that the power to make amendment has to be found. in Art. 248 read with
item 97 of List 1. It is further urged that the word "amendment" in
Art. 368 means that the provisions in the Constitution can be changed so as to
important upon them And that this power is of a limited character and does not
authorise Parliament to make any addition to, alteration of or deletion of any
,provision of the Constitution, including the provision contained in Part III.
So Art. 368 authorises only those amendments which have the effect of improving
the Constitution. Then it is urged that amendment permissible under Art. 368 is
subject to certain implied limitations and the these limitations are that basic
features of the Constitution cannot be amended at all. An attempt was made to
indicate some of these basic features, as, f( example, the provisions in Part
III, the federal structure, the republican character of the State, elected Parliament
and State Legislatures on-the basis of adult suffrage, control by the judiciary
and so on, and it is. said thatan amendment under Art. 3 69 is subject to the
implied limi(1) (1952] S.C.R. 89.
L3Sup.CI/67-7 822 tations that these basic
features and others of the kind cannot be, changed. Thus in effect the argument
is that there is a very limited power of amendment under the Constitution.
It is further urged that apart from these
implied limitations, there is an express limitation under Art. 13(2) and the
word "law in that Article includes an amendment of the Constitution. The
argument thus in the alternative is that as the word "law" in Art.
13(2) includes a constitutional amendment, no amendment can be made in Part HI
under Art. 368 which would actually take away or abridge the rights guaranteed
under that Part. In effect, it is said that even if there are no implied
limitations to amend the Constitution under Art. 368, Art. 13(2) is an express
limitation insofar as the power to amend Part III is concerned and by virtue of
Art. 13(2) the rights guaranteed under Part III cannot be taken away or
abridged under Art.
368, though it is conceded that Part III may
be amended by way of enlarging the rights contained therein.
Another line of argument is that in any case
it was necessary to take action under the proviso to Art. 368 and as that was
not done the Seventeenth Amendment is not valid.
It is urged that Art. 2,26 is seriously
affected by the provisions contained in the Seventeenth Amendment and that
amounts to an amendment of Aft. 226 and in consequence action under theproviso
was necessary. It is also urged that Art. 245 was addition of a number of Acts
in the Ninth 13 (2) and therefore also it was necessary to take action under
the proviso. It is further urged that it was not competent for Parliament to
amend the Constitution by putting a large number of Acts in the Ninth Schedule
as the power to legislate with respect to land is solely within the. competence
of State Legislatures and that is another reason why the addition to the Ninth
Schedule read with Art.
31 B should be struck down.
Lastly an argument had been advanced which we
may call the argument of fear. It is said that if Art.368 is held to confer
full to amend each and every part of the Constitution as has been held in
Sankari Prasad's case(1). Parliament May do all kinds of things, which were
never intended, under this unfettered power and may, for example, abolish
elected legislatures, abolish the President or change the present form of
Government into a Presedential type like the United States. Constitution or do
away with the federal structure altogether. So it is urged that, we
should,interpret Art.
368 in such a way that Parliament may not be
able to doall these things. In effect this argument of fear has been put
forward to reinforce the contention that this Court should (1)[1952] S.C.R. 89.
823 hold that there are some implied
limitations on the amending power and these implied limitations should be that
there is no power any where in the Constitution to change the basic features of
the Constitution to which reference has already been made. This is in brief the
submission on behalf of the petitioners and the interveners who support them.
The submission on behalf of the Union of
India and the States may now be summarised. It is urged that Art. 368 not only
provides procedure or amendment but also contains in it the power to amend the
Constitution. It is further urged that the word "amendment" in law
does not merely mean making such changes in the Constitution as would improve
it but includes the power to make any addition to the Constitution, any
alteration of any of the existing provisions and its substitution by another
provisions, and any deletion of any particular provision of the Constitution.
In .effect, it is urged that even if the word "amendment" used in
Art. 368 does not take in the power to abrogate the entire 'Constitution and
replace it by another new Constitution, it certainly means that any provisions
of the Constitution may be changed and this change can be in the form of
addition to, alteration of or deletion of any provision of the Constitution. So
long therefore as the Constitution is not entirely abrogated and replaced by anew
Constitution at one stroke, the power of amendment would enable Parliament tomake
all changes in the existing Constitution by addition, alteration or deletion.
Subject only to co repeal being not possible, the power of amendment contained
in Art.
368 is unfettered. It is further urged that
there can be no implied limitations on the power to amend and the limitations
if any on this. power must be found hi express terms in the Article providing
for-amendment. It is conceded that there may be an express limitation not
merely in the Article providing for amendment, but in some other part of the
Constitution. But it is said that if that is so, there must be a clear
provision to that effect. In the absence of express limitations, therefore,
there can be no implied limitations ,on the power to amend the Constitution
contained in Art. 368 and that power will take in all changes whether by way of
addition, alteration or deletion, subject only to this that the power of
amendment may riot contain the, power to abrogate and repeal the entire Constitution
and substitute it with a new one.
It is then urged that there is no express
provision in Art.368 itself so far as any amendment relating to the substance
of the amending power is concerned-, die only limitations in Art, 368 are as to
procedure and courts can only see that the procedure as indicated in Art. 368
is followed before an amendment can be said to be valid. It is further urged
that the word "law", in Art. 13 does not include an amendment of the
Constitution and only 824 moans law as made. under the legislative provisions
contained in Chapter, I of Part XI read with, Chapters II and III of Part V of
the. Constitution and Chapters III and V of Part VI thereof. In effect it is a
law which is made under the Constitution which included in the word
"law" in Art. 13(2) and not an amendment to the Constitution under
Art. 368.
As to Articles 226 and 245 and the necessity
of taking action under the proviso to Art. 368, it is urged that there is no
change in Arts. 226 and 245on account of any provision in the Seventeenth
Amendment and therefore no action under the proviso was necessary. it is only
direct change in Arts. 226 and 245 which would require following the procedure
as to ratification or at any rate such change in other Articles which would
have the effect of directly compelling change in Arts 226 and 245 and that in
the present case no such direct compulsion arises.
Lastly as to the argument of fear it is urged
that there is always a provision with respect to amendment in written federal Constitutions.
Such a provision may be rigid or flexible. In our Constitution Art. 368
provides for a comparatively flexible provision for amendment and there is' no
reason to make it rigid by implying any limitations on that power. Further
there Is no reason to suppose that all those things will be done by Parliament
which are being urged to deny the power under Art. 368 which flows naturally
from its terms.
Besides the above, reliance is also placed on
behalf of the Union of India and the States on the doctrine. of stare decisis.
It is urged that since the decision of this Court in Sankari Prasad's case(1),
sixteen further amendments have been made by Parliament on the faith of that
decision involving over 200 Articles of the Constitution. The amendments relating
to Part III have been mainly with respect to agrarian reforms resulting in
transfers of title of millions of acres of land in favour of millions of
people. Therefore', even though Sankari Prasad's case(1) has stood only for
fifteen years there has been a vast agrarian revolution effected on the faith
of that decision and this Court should not now go back on what was decided in
that case. Further, besides the argument based on state decisis, it is urged on
the basis of certain decisions of this Court that the unanimous decision in
Sankari Prasad's case(1) which had stood practically unchallenged for
about'15'years till the decision in Sajjan Singh's case(2), should not be
over-ruled unless it is found to be incorrect by a large majority of the Judges
constituting this Special Bench. It is urged that if the present Bench is more
or less evenly divided it should not over-rule the unanimous decision in'
Sankari Prasad's case(1) by a Majority of one.
(1) (1952] S.C.R. 89.
(2) [1965] 1 S.C.R. 933 825 We shall first
take Art, 368. It is found in Part XX of the Constitution which is headed.
Amendment of the Constitution" and is the only Article in that Part. That
Part thus provides specifically for the amendment of the Constitution, and the
first question that arises is whether it provides power for the amendment of
the Constitution as well as the procedure for doing so. It is not disputed that
the procedure for amendment of the Constitution is to be found in Art. 368, but
what is in dispute is whether Art.
368 confers power also in that behalf. Now
the procedure for the amendment of the Constitution is this: The amendment is
initiated by the introduction of a Bill in either House of Parliament. The Bill
has to be passed in each House by a majority of the total membership of that
House and by a Majority of not less two-thirds of the members of that House
present and voting. After it is so passed, it has to be presented to the
President for his assent. On such presentation if the President assents to the
Bill, Art. 3-68 provides that the Constitution shall stand amended in
accordance with the terms of the Bill. Further there is a proviso for
ratification with respect to certain Articles and other provisions of the
Constitution including Art. 368, and those matters can only be amended if the
Bill passed by the two Houses by necessary majority is ratified by the
legislatures of not less than one-half of the States by resolutions to that
effect. In such a case the Bill cannot be presented for his assent to the President
until necessary ratification is available. But when the. necessary ratification
has been made, the Bill with respect to these matters is then presented to the
President and on his assent being given, the Constitution stands amended. in
accordance with the terms of the Bill.
The argument is that there is no express
provision in terms in Art. 368 conferring power on Parliament to amend the
Constitution, and in this connection our attention has been invited to an
analogous provision in the Constitution of Ireland in Art. 46, where cl. 1
provides that any provision of the Constitution, may be amended in the manner
provided in that Article, and then follows the procedure for amendment in
clauses 2 to 5. Reference is also made to similar provisions in. other
constitutions, but it is unnecessary to refer to them. . It is urged that as
Art. 368 has nothing comparable to cl. I of Art. 46 of the Irish Constitution,
the power to amend the Constitution is not in.
Art. 3 68 and must .be. found elsewhere. We
are not prepared to accept this argument. The fact that Art. 368 is not in two
parts, the first part indicating that the Constitution shall be amended in the
manner provided thereafter, and the second part indicating the procedure for
amendment, does not mean that the power to amend the Constitution is not
contained in Art. 368 itself. The very fact that a 826 separate Part has been
devoted in the Constitution for amendment thereof and there is only one Article
in that Part shows that both the power to amend and the procedure for amendment
are to be found in Art. 368. Besides, the words "the Constitution shall
stands amended in accordance 'with the terms of the Bill" in Art. 368
clearly in our opinion provide for the power to amend after the procedure has
been followed. It appears that our Constitution-makers were apparently thinking
of economy of words and elegance of language in enacting Art. 368 in the terms
in which it appears and that is why it is not in two parts on the model of
Art.46 of the Irish Constitution. But there can in our opinion. be not doubt,
when a separate Part was provided headed "Amendment of the
Constitution" that the power to amend the Constitution must also be
contained in Art. 368 which is the only Article in that Part. If there was any doubt
about thematter, that doubt in our opinion is resolved by the words to which we
have already referred namely "the Constitution shall stand amended in the
terms of the Bill". These words can only mean that the. power is there to
amend the Constitution after the procedure has been followed.
It is however urged that the power to amend
the Constitution is not to be found in Art. 368 but is contained in the
residuary power of Parliament in Art. 48 read with item 97 of List 1. It is
true that Art. 248 read with item 97 of List I, insofar as it provides for
residuary power of legislation, is very wide in its scope and the argument that
the, power to amend the Constitution is contained in this provision appears
prima facie attractive 'in view of the width of the residuary power. But we
fail to see why when there is a whole Part devoted to the amendment of the Constitution
the power to amend should not be found in that Part, if it can be reasonably
found there and why Art. 368 should only be confined to providing for procedure
for amendment. It is true that the marginal note to Art. 368 is "procedure
for amendment of the Constitution", but. the marginal note cannot control
the meaning of the words in the Article itself, and we have no doubt that the
words "the Constitution shall stand amended in accord the power of
amendment. If we were to compare the language of cls. 2 to 5of Art. 46of the
Irish Constitution which prescribes the procedure for amendment, we find no
words therein comparable to these words in Art. 368. These words clearly are
comparable to cl. I of Art. 46-of the Irish Constitution and must be rod as
conferring power on Parliament to amend the Constitution. Besides it is
remarkable in contrast that Art. 248 read with List I does not in terms mention
the amendment of the Constitution. while therefore there is a whole Part
devoted to the amendment of the Constitution, we do not find any specific
mention of the 827 amendment of the Constitution in Art. 248 or in any entry of
List 1.
It would in the circumstances be more
appropriate to read in power in Art. 3 68 in view of the, words which we have
already referred to than in Art. 248 read with item 97 of List I. Besides it is
a historical fact to which we can refer that originally the intention was to
vest residuary power in States, and if that intention had been eventually
carried out, it would have been impossible for any one to argue that the power
to amend the Constitution was to be found in the residuary power if it had been
vested in the States and not in the Union. The mere fact that during the
passage of the Constitution by the Constituent Assembly, residuary power was
finally vested in the Union would not therefore mean that it includes the power
to amend the Constitution. On a comparison of the scheme, of the words in Art
368 and the scheme of the words in Art. 248 read with item 97 of List 1,
therefore, there is no doubt in our mind that both the procedure and power to
amend the Constitution are to be found in Art. 368 and they are not to be found
in Art. 248 read with item 97 of List I which provides for residuary
legislative power of Parliament.
There is in our opinion another reason why
the power to amend the Constitution cannot found in Art. 248 read with item 97
of List 1. The Constitution is the fundamental law and no law passed under mere
legislative power conferred by the Constitution can affect any change, in the
Constitution unless there is an express power to that effect given in the
Constitution itself. But subject to such express power given by the
Constitution itself, the fundamental law, namely the Constitution, cannot be
changed by a law passed under the legislative provisions contained in the
Constitution as all legislative acts passed under the power conferred by the Constitution
must conform to the Constitution can make no change therein. There are a number
of Articles in the Constitution, which expressly provide for amendment by law,
as,. for example, 3, 4, 10, 59(3), 65(3), 73(2), 97, 98(3), 106, 120(2), 135,
137, 142(1), 146(2), 148(3), 149, 169, 171(2), 196, 187(3), 189(3), 194(3),
195, 210(2), 221(2). 225, 229(2), 239(1), 241(3), 283(1) and (2), 285(2), 287,
306(1), 313, 345, 373, Sch. V. cl. 7 and Sch.
VI, cl. 21,, and so far as these Articles are
concerned they can be amended by Parliament by. ordinary law-making process.
But so far as the other Articles are concerned they can only be amended by
amendment of 'the Constitution under Art. 368. Now Art. 245 which gives power
to make law for the whole or any part of the territory of India by Parliament
is "subject to the provisions of this Constitution" and any law made
by Parliament whether under Art.
246 read with List I or under Art. 248 read
with item 97 of List I be subject to the provisions of the Constitution. If
therefore the power to amend the Constitution is contained in Art. 248 828 read
with item 97 of List 1, that power has to be exercised subject to the
provisions of the Constitution and cannot be used to change the fundamental law
(namely, the Constitution) itself. But it is argued that Art. 368 which
provides a special procedure for amendment of the Constitution should be read
along with Arts. 245 248, and so read it would be open to amend any provision
of the Constitution by law passed under Art. 248 on the ground that Art. 248 is
subject to Art. 368 and therefore the two together give power to Parliament to
pass a law under Art.
248 which will amend even those provisions of
the Constitution which are not expressly made amendable by law passed under the
legislative power of Parliament. This inour opinion is arguing in a circle.If
the fundamental law (ie. the Constitution) cannot be I changed by any law
passed under the legislative powers contained therein, for legislation so
passed must conform to the fundamental law, we fail to see how a law, passed
under the residuary power which is nothing, more than legislative power
conferred on parliament under the Constitution, can change the Constitution
(namely, the fundamental law) Itself.
We,may in this connection refer to the
following passage in The Law.and the Constitution by W. Ivor Jennings (1933
Ed.) at p. 51 onwards :"A written constitution is thus the fundamental law
of a country, the express embodiment of the doctrine of the region of law. All
public uthorities-legislative, administrative and judical-take their powers
directly or indirectly from it.....Whatever the nature of the written
constitution it is clear that there "is a fundamental distinction between
constitutional law and the rest of the law........ There is a clear separation,
therefore, between the constitutional law and the rest of the law." It is
because of this difference between the. fundamental law (namely, the
Constitution) and the law passed under the legislative provisions of the
Constitution that it is not possible in the absence of an express provision to
that effect in the fundamental law to ,change the fundamental law by ordinary
legislation passed thereunder, for such ordinary legislation must always
conform to the fundamental law (i.e.
the Constitution). If the power to amend the
Constitution is to be found in Art. 248 read with item 97 of List 1. It will
mean that ordinary legislation passed under fundamental law would amend that
law and this cannot be done unless there is express provision as in Art. 3 etc.
to that effect In the absence of such express provisions any law passed under
the legislative powers granted under the fundamental'law cannot amend it. So if
we were to hold that the power to amend the 829 Constitution is comprised
in-Art. 248, that would mean thatno amendment-,of the Constitution would be
possible at all except to the extent expressly provided in various Articles to
which we have referred already, for the power to legislate under Art. 245 read
with Art. 248 is itself subject to the Constitution. Therefore reading Art. 368
and considering the scheme of the legislative powers conferred by Articles 245
and 248 read with item 97 of List I" this to our mind is clear, firstly
that the power to amend the, Constitution is to be found in Art. 368 itself,
and secondly, that the power to amend the Constitution can never reside in Art.
245 and Art. 248 read with item 97 of List 1, for that would make any amendment
of the Constitution impossible except with respect to the express-provisions
contained in certain Articles thereof for amendment by law-.
We may in this connection add that all this
argument that power to amend the Constitution is to be found in Art. 245 and
Art. 248 read with item 97 of List I has been based on one accidental
circumstance, and that accidental circumstance is that the procedure for
amendment of the Constitution contained in Art. 368 is more or less assimilated
to the procedure for making ordinary laws under the Constitution. The argument
is that constitutional amendment is also passed by the two Houses of
Parliament, and is assented to by the President like ordinary legislation, with
this difference that a special majority is required for certain purposes and a
special majority plus ratification is required for certain other purposes. It
may be admitted that the procedure for amendment under Art. 368 is somewhat
similar to the procedure for passing ordinary legislation under the
Constitution. Even so, as pointed out by Sir Ivor Jennings in the passage
already quoted, there is a clear separation between constitutional law and the
rest of the law and that must never be forgotten. An amendment to the
Constitution is a constitutional law and as observed in Sankari Prasad's
case(1) is in exercise of constituent power; passing of ordinary law is in
exercise of ordinary legislative power and is clearly different from the power
to amend the Constitution. We may in this connection refer, for example, to
Art. V of other U.S. Constitution, which provides for the, amendment thereof.
It will be clearly seen that the power contained in Art. V of the U.S.
Constitution is not ordinary legislative
power and no one can possibly call it ordinary legislative power, because the
procedure provided for the amendment of the Constitution in Art. V differs
radically from the procedure provided for ordinary legislation, for example,
the President's assent is not required constitutional amendment under Art. V of
the U.S. Constitution,; Now if Art. 368 also had made a similar departure from
the procedure provided for ordinary legislation, it could never have (1) [1952
] 1 S. C. R. 89 830 said that Art. 368 merely contained the procedure for
amendment and that what emerges after that procedure is followed is ordinary law
of the same quality and nature as emerges after following the procedure for
passing ordinary law. If, for example, the assent of the President which is to
be found in Art. 368 had not been there and the Constitution would have stood
amended after the Bill had been passed by the two Houses by necessary majority
and after ratification by not less than one-half of the States where so
required , it could never have been argued that the power to amend the
Constitution was contained in Art. 245 and 248 read with item 97 of List I and
Art. 368 merely contained the procedure.
We are however of opinion that we should look
at the quality and nature of what is done under Art. 368 and not lay so much
stress on the similarity of the procedure contained in Art. 368 with the
procedure for ordinary lawmaking. If we thus look at the quality and nature of
what is done under Art. 368, we find that it is the exercise of constituent
power for the purpose of amending the Constitution itself land is very
different from the exercise of ordinary legislative power for passing laws
which must be in conformity with the Constitution and cannot go against any
provision thereof, unless there is express provision to that effect to which we
have already referred. If we thus refer to the nature and quality of what is
done under Art. 368, we immediately See that what emerges after the procedure
in Art. 368 is gone through is not ordinary law which emerges after the
legislative procedure contained in the Constitution is gone through. Thus Art.
368 provides for the coming into existence of what may be called the
fundamental law in the form of an amendment of the Constitution and therefore
what emerges after the procedure under Art. 368 is gone through is not ordinary
legislation but an amendment of the Constitution which becoming a part of the
fundamental law itself, by virtue of the words contained in Art. 368 to the
effect that the Constitution shall stand amended in accordance with the terms
of the 'Bill.
It is urged in this connection on behalf of
the Union of India that even though the assent of the President is required
under Aft. 368, the ;President must assent thereto and cannot withhold his
assent as is possible in the case of ordinary law in view of Art. III of the
Constitution, for the words "that he withholds assent therefrom"
found in Art.
III are not to be found in Art. 368. It is
however difficult to accept the argument on behalf of the Union that the
President cannot withhold his assent when a Bill for amendment of the
Constitution is presented to him. Article '368 provides that a Bill for the
amendment of the, Constitution shall be presented to the President for his
assent. It further provides 831 that upon such assent by the President, the
Constitution shall, stand amended. That in our opinion postulates that if
assent is not given, the Constitution cannot be amended.
Whether a President will ever withhold his
assent in our form of Government is a different matter altogether, but as we
road Art. 368 we cannot. hold that the President is bound to assent and cannot
withhold his assent when a Bill for amendment of the Constitution is presented
to him. We are of opinion that 'the President can refuse to give his assent
when a Bill for amendment of the Constitution is presented to him, the result
being that the Bill altogether falls, for there is no specific provision for
anything further to be done,: about the Bill in Art. 368 as there is in Art.
III.
We may in this. connection refer to the
different language used in cl. 5 of Art. 46 of the Irish Constitution which
says that "a Bill containing a proposal for the amendment of this
Constitution shall be signed by the President Forthwith upon his being
satisfied that the provisions of this Article have been complied with, in
respect thereof'. It will be seen therefore that if the intention kinder Art.
368 had been that the President cannot withhold his assent, we would have found
language similar in terms to that in cl. 5 of Art. 46 of the Irish
Constitution.
We thus see that in one respect at any rate
Art. 368 even on its present terms differs from the power of the President in
connection with ordinary legislation under the Constitution and that is if the
President withholds his assent the Bill for amendment of' the Constitution
immediately falls. We cannot accept that the procedure provided under the
proviso to Art. 111 can apply in such a case, for this much cannot be disputed
that so far as the procedure for amendment of the Constitution is concerned we
must look to Art. 368 only and nothing else. In any case the mere fact that the
procedure in Art. 368 is very much assimilated. to the procedure for passing
ordinary legislation is no reason for, holding that what emerges after the
procedure under Art. 368 is followed is ordinary law and no more. We repeat
that we must look at the quality and nature of what is done under Art. 368, and
that is, the amendment of the Constitution.
If we look at that we must bold that what
emerges is not ordinary law passed under the Constitution but something which
has the effect of amending the fundamental law itself which could not be done
by ordinary legislative process under the Constitution unless there is express
provision to that effect. We have already referred to such express provisions
in various Articles, but Art. 368 cannot be treated as such an Article, for it
deals specifically with the amendment of the Constitution as a whole.
It is also remarkable to note in this
connection that the, word "law" which has been used in so many
Articles of 'the Consti832 tution has been avoided apparently with great care
in Art.
368. We again refer to the concluding words
368 which says that the "Constitution shall stand amended in accordance
with the terms of the Bill. Now it is well-known that in the case of ordinary
legislation as soon both Houses and has received the assent of the main part of
Art. stand amended in ac it is well-known that as the Bill is passed by of the
President it becomes an Act. But Art. 368 provides that as soon as the Bill for
amendment of the Constitution has been passed in accordance with the procedure
provided there in the Constitution shall stand amendmend in accordance with the
terms of the Bill. These words in our opinion have significance of their own.
It is also remarkable that these words clearly show the difference between the,
quality of what emerges after the procedure under Art., 368 is followed and
what happens when ordinary law-making procedure is followed. Under Art. III, in
the case of ordinary lawmaking when a Bill is passed by the two Houses of
parliament it is presented to the President and the President shall declare
either that he assents to the Bill or that he withholds assent therefrom. But
it is remarkable that Art.
111 does not provide that when the Bill has been
assented to by the President it becomes an Act' The reason for this is that the
Bill assented to by the President though it may become law is still not
declared by Art. I I I to be a law, for such law is open to challenge in courts
on various ,grounds, namely, on the ground that it violates any fundamental
rights, or on the ground that Parliament was not competent to pass it or on the
ground that it is in breach of any provision of the Constitution. On the other
hand we find that when a Bill for the amendment of the Constitution is passed
by requisite majority and assented to by the President, the Constitution itself
,declares that the Constitution shall stand amended in accordance with the
terms of the Bill. Thereafter what courts can see is whether the procedure
provided in Art. 368 has been followed, for if that is not done, the
Constitution cannot stand amended in accordance with the terms of the Bill. But
if the procedure has been followed, the Constitution stands amended, and there
is no question of testing the amendment of the Constitution thereafter on the
anvil of fundamental rights or in any other way as in the case of ordinary
legislation. In view of an this we have no doubt thateven though. by accident
the procedure provided in the Constitution for amendment thereof is very akin
to the procedure for passing ordinary legislation, the power contained in Art.
368 is still not ordinary legislative power but constituent power for the
specific purpose of amendment of the Constitution; and it is the quality of
that power which determines the nature of what emerges after the procedure in
Art. 368 has been followed and what thus emerges is not ordinary legislation
but fundamental law which cannot be tested,. for example, under Art. 13(2) of
the Constitution or under any other provision of the Constitution.
833 We may briefly refer to an argument on
behalf of the Union of India that the amending power contained in Art. 368 is
same sovereign power which was possessed by the Constituent Assembly when it made
the Constitution and therefore it is not subject to any fetters of any kind. We
do not think it necessary to enter into the academic question as to where
sovereignty re-sides and whether legal sovereignty is in the people and
political. sovereignty in the body which has the power to amend the
Constitution and vice versa. In our view the words of Art. 368 clearly confer
the power to amend the Constitution and also provide the procedure for doing
so, and that in our opinion is enough for the purpose of deciding whether the
Seventeenth Amendment is valid or not.
Further as we have already stated, the power
conferred under Art. 368 is constituent power to change the fundamental law
i.e. the Constitution, and is distinct and different from the ordinary legislative
power conferred on Parliament by various other provisions in the Constitution.
So long as this distinction is kept in mind Parliament would have the power
under Art. 368 to amend the Constitution and what Parliament does under Art.
368 is not ordinary law-making which is subject to Art. 13 (2) or any other
Article of the Constitution. What is the extent of the power conferred on
Parliament and whether there are any limitations on it--express or implied-will
be considered by us presently.
But we have no doubt, without entering into
the question of sovereignty and of whether Art. 368 confers the same sovereign
power on Parliament as the Constituent Assembly had when framing the
Constitution, that Art. 368 does confer power on Parliament subject to the procedure
provided therein for amendment of any provision of-the Constitution..
This brings us to the scope and extent of the
power conferred, for amendment under Art. 368. It is urged that Art. 368 only
gives power to amend the Constitution.
Recourse is had on behalf of the petitioners
to the dictionary meaning of the word, "amendment". It is said that
amendment implies and means improvement in detail and cannot take in any change
in the basic features of the Constitution. Reference in this connection may be
made tothe following meaning of the word "'amend" in the Oxford
English Dictionary, namely, "to make professed improvements in a, measure
before Parliament; formally, to after in detail, though practically it may be
to alter its principle, so as to thwart ". This meaning lit any rate does
not support the case of the petitioners that amendment merely means such change
as results in improvement in detail. It shows that in-law though amendment MAY
professedly, be intended to makeimprovements and to alter only in detail, in
reality, it may make a radical change in the provision which is amended. In any
case, as was pointed out in Sajjan Singh's case(1) the word "amend"
or "amendment"' is well under(1) [1965] 1 S.C.R. 933.
834 stood in law and will certainly include
any change whether by way of addition or alteration or deletion of any
provision in the Constitution. This is no reason to suppose that when the word.
"amendment" of the Constitution was being used in Art. 368, the
intention was to give any meaning less than what we have stated above. To say
that "amendment" in law only means a change 'which results in
improvement would make amendments impossible, for whatis improvement of an
existing law is a matter of opinion and what, for example, the legislature may
consider an improvement may not be so considered by others. It is therefore in
our opinion impossible to introduce in the concept of amendment as used in Art.
368 any idea of improvement as to details of the Constitution. The word
"amendment" used in Art. 368 must therefore be given its full meaning
as used in law and that .means that by amendment an existing Constitution or
law can be changed and this change can take the form either of addition to the
existing provisions, or alteration of existing provisions and their
substitution by others or deletion of certain provisions. altogether. In this
connection reference has been made-to contrast certain other provisions of the
Constitution, where, for example the word "amend" has been followed
by such words as "by way of addition, variance or repeal" (see Sixth
Schedule, paragraph 2-1) and more or less similar expressions in other
Articles,of the Constitution.
it is very difficult to say fact, that no
such words appear in Art. make any difference, for the meaning of the word why
this was done. But the 368 does not in our, mind "amendmend" in law
is clearly as indicated above by us and the presence or sense, of explanatory
words of the nature indicated above do not in our opinion make any difference.
The question whether the power of amendment
given by Art.
368 also 'includes the power to abrogate the
Constitution completely and to replace it by an entire new Constitution, does
not really arise in the present case, for the Seventeenth Amendment has not
done any such thing and need not be considered. It is enough to say that it may
be open to doubt whether the power of amendment contained in Art.
568 goes to the extent of completely
abrogating the present Constitution and substituting it by an entirely new one.
But short of that, we are of opinion that the
power to amend includes the power to add any provision to the Constitution. to
alter any provision and substitute any other provision in its place and to
delete any provision.
The Seventeenth Amendment is merely in
exercise of the power of amendment a indicated above and cannot be struck down
on the ground that it goes beyond the power conferred on Parliament to amend
the Constitution by Art. 368.
The next question that arises is whether
there is any limitation on the power of amendment as explained by us above.
835 Limitations may be of two kinds, namely,
express or implied.
So far as express limitations are concerned,
there are none such in' Art. 368. When it speaks of the "amendment of this
Constitution it obviously and clearly refers to amendment of any provision
thereof, including the provisions contained in Part III relating to fundamental
rights. Whether Art. 13(2) is an express limitation on the power of amendment
will be considered by us law, but so far as, Art. 368 is concerned there are no
limitation whatsoever in the matter of substance on the amending power and any
provision of the Constitution, be it in Part III and any other Part, can be
amended under Art. 368.
The next question is whether there are any
implied limitations on the power of amendment contained in Art. 368, and this
Wags us to the argument that there are certain basic features of the
Constitution which cannot be amended at all and there is an implied limitation
on the power of amendment contained in Art. 5-68 so far as these basic features
are concerned. We may in this connection refer to the view prevailing amongst
jurists in the United States of America as to whether there are any plied
limitations on the power of amendment contained in Art. V of the U.S.
Constitution.
There are two lines of thought in this matter
in the United States. Some jurists take the, view that there are certain
implied limitations on the power to amend contained in Art.
V of the U.S. Constitution. These are said to
be with respect to certain basic features, like, the republican character of
Government, the federal structure etc. On the other hand, it is that the more
prevalent view amongst jurists in the United States is that there are no implied
limitations on the scope of the amending power in Art. V of the U.S.
Constitution. Willis on the Constitutional Law of the United States of America
(1936-Edition says that probably the correct position is that the amending
power embraces everything; in other words there are no legal limitations
whatever on the power of amendment, except what is expressly provided, in Art.
V : (seediscussion on pp.
1.22 to 127). Even with respect to these
express limitations, Munro in The Government of the United States (Fifth
Edition) at p. 77 says that even these express limitations can be removed and
one of the ways of doing so is "to remove, the exception by a preliminary
amendment and thus clear the way for further action". Besides, as a matter
of fact there is no decision of the Supreme Court of the United States holding
that there are implied limitations on the power of amendment contained in Art.
V of the U.S.
Constitution and all amendments so far made
in the United States have been upheld by the Supreme Court there in the few
cases that have been taken to-it for testing the validity of the amendments.
836 We have given careful consideration to
the argument that certain basic features of our Constitution cannot be amended
under Art. 368 and have come to, the conclusion that no limitations can be and
should be implied upon the power of amendment under Art. 368. One. reason for
coming to this conclusion is that if we were to accept that certain basic
features of the Constitution cannot be amended under Art.
368, it will lead to the position that any
amendment made to any Article of the Constitution would be liable to challenge
before courts on the ground that it amounts to amendment of a basic feature.
Parliament would thus never be able to know what amendments it can make in the
Constitution and what it cannot; for, till a complete catalogue of basic
features of the Constitution is available, it would be impossible to make any
amendment under Art. 368 with any certainty that it would be upheld by courts.
If such an implied limitation were to be put on the power of amendment
contained in Art. 368, it would only be the courts which would have the power
to decide what are basic features of the Constitution and then to declare
whether a particular amendment is valid or not on the ground that it amends a
particular basic feature or not. The .result would be that every amendment made
in the Constitution would provide a harvest of legal wrangles so much so that
Parliament may never know what provisions can be amended and what cannot.
The power to amend being a constituent power
cannot in our opinion for these reasons be held subject to any implied
limitations thereon on the ground that certain basic features of the
Constitution cannot be amended. We fail to see why if there was any intention
to make any part of the Constitution unamendable, the Constituent Assembly
failed to indicate it expressly in Art. 368. If, for example, the
Constitution-makers intended certain provisions in the Constitution, and Part
III in particular, to be not amendable, we can see no reason why it was not so
stated in Art. 368. On the clear words of Art. 368 which provides for amendment
of the Constitution which means any provision thereof,. we cannot infer an
implied limitation on the power of amendment of any provision of the
Constitution', be it basic or otherwise. Our conclusion is that constituent
power, like that contained,in Art. 368, can only be subject to express
limitations and not to any implied limitations so,far as substance of the amendments
are concerned and in the absence of anything in Art. 368 making any provision
of the Constitution unamendable, it Must be held that the power to. amend in
Art. .3 68 reaches every provision of the Constitution and can be used to amend
any provision thereof provided the procedure indicated, in Art. 368 is
followed.
Copious references were made during the
course of arguments to debates in Parliament and it is urged that it is open to
this 837 Court to look into the debates in order to interpret Art.
368 to find out the intention of the
Constitution makers.
We are of opinion that we cannot and should
not look into the debates that took place in the Constituent Assembly to
determine the interpretation of Art. 368 and the scope and extent of the provision
contained therein. It may be conceded that historical background and perhaps
what was accepted or what was rejected by the Constituent Assembly while the
Constitution was being framed, may be taken into account in finding out the
scope and extent of Art. 368.
But we have no doubt that what was spoken in
the debates in the Constituent Assembly cannot and should not be looked intoin
order to interpret Art. 368. Craies on Statute Law (Sixth Edition) at p. 128
says that "it is not permissible in discussing the meaning of an obscure
enactment, to refer to 'parliamentary history' of a statute, in the sense of
the debates which took place in Parliament when the statute was under
consideration", and supports his view with reference to a large number of
English cases. The same is the view in Maxwell on Interpretation of Statutes,
(11th Edition) p. 26.
Crawford on Statutory Construction (1940
Edition) at p. 340 says that resort may not be had to debates to ascertain
legislative Intent though historical background in which the legislation came
to be passed, can be taken into consideration-.
In Administrator General of Bengal v. Prem
Lai Mullick(1), the Privy Council held that "proceedings of the
legislature cannot be referred to as legitimate aids to the construction of the
Act in which they result." In Baxter v. Commissioner of Taxation(2), it
was said that reference to historical facts can be made in order to interpret a
statute. There was however no reference to the debates in order to arrive at
the meaning of a particular provision of the Constitution there in dispute.
In A. K. Gopalan v. the State of Madras(3),
Kania C.J. referring to the debates and reports of the Drafting Committee of
the Constituent Assembly in respect of the words of Art.
21 observed at p. I 10 that they might not be
read to control the meaning of the Article. In that case all that was accepted
was that "due process of law" which was a term used in the. U.S.
Constitution, was not accepted for the purpose of Art. 21 which used the words
44 the procedure established by law". Patanjali Sastri J. (at p. 202) also
refused to look at the debates 'and particularly the speeches made in order to
determine the meaning of Art. 21.
Fazl Ali, J. (at p. 158) was of opinion that
the pro(1) [1895] 22 LA. 107. (2) [1907] 4 C.L.R. 1087.
(3) [1950] S.C.R. 88.
Sup.CI/67-8 838 ceedings and discuss ions In
Constituent Assembly were not relevant for the purpose of construing the
expressions used in Art. 2 1.
Again in The Automobile Transport (Rajasthan)
Limited v. the State of Rajasthan(.'), this Court looked into the historical
background but refused to look into the debates in order to determine the
meaning of the provisions of the Constitution in dispute in that case.
We are therefore of opinion that it is not
possible to read the speeches made in the Constituent Assembly in order to
interpret An. 368 or to define its extent and scope and to determine what
it,takes in and what it does not. As to this historical facts.. namely, what
was accepted or what was avoided in the Constituent Assembly in connection with
Art.
368, it is enough to say that we have not
been able to find any help from the material relating to this. There were
proposals for restricting the power of amendment under Art.
368 and making fundamental rights immune from
and there were counter proposals before the Constituent assembly for making the
power, of amendment all embracing They were all either dropped or negatived and
in the circumstanses are of no help in determining the interpretation of Art.
368 which must be interpreted on the words thereof as they finally found place
in the Constitution, and on those words we have no doubt that there are no
implied limitations of any kind on the power to amend given therein.
An argument is also raised that limitations
on the power to amend the Constitution can be found in the preamble to the
Constitution. As to that we may refer only to in re: the Berubari Union and
Exchange of Enclaves(2) with respect to the value of the preamble to the Constitution
and its importance therein. It was observed in that case unanimously by a Bench
of nine judges that "although it may be correct to describe the preamble
as a key to the mind of the Constitution-makers, it form no part of the
Constitution and cannot be regarded as the source of any substantive power
which the body of the Constitution alone can confer on the Government ,
expressly or by implication. This is equally true to prohibitions and
limitations". The Court there was considering whether the preamble could
in any way limit the power of Parliament to cede any part of the national
teritory and held that it was not correct to say that "the preamble in any
way limit the power of Parliament to cede parts of the national
territory". On a parity, of reasoning we are of opinion that the preamble
cannot prohibit or control in any way or impose any implied prohibitions or
limitations oft Me power to amend the Constitution contained in Art. 368.
(1) [1963] 1 S.C.R. 491. (2) [1960] 3 S.C.R.
250.
839 This brings us to the question whether
the word "law" in Art. 13 (2) includes an amendment of the
Constitution, and therefore there is an express provision in Art. 1 3 (2) which
at least limits the power of amendment under Art. 3 68 to this extent that by
such amendment fundamental rights guaranteed by Part 111 cannot be taken away
or abridged. We have already pointed out that in Sankari Prasad's case(1) as
well as Sajjan Singh's case(1) it has already been held, in one case
unanimously and in the other by majority, that the word "law" in Art.
13(2) does not include an amendment of the Constitution, and it is the
correctness of this view which is being imputed before this Bench, Article 13
is in three parts. The first part lays down that "all laws in force in the
territory of India immediately before the commencement of this Constitution,
insofar as they are inconsistent with the provisions of this Part, shall, to
the extent of such inconsistency, be void". Further all previous
constitutional,provisions were repealed by Art. 395 which provided that
"'the Indian Independence Act, 1947, and the Government of India Act,
1935, together with all enactments amending or supplementing the latter Act,
but not including the Abolition of Privy Council Jurisdiction Act, 1949, are
hereby repealed."' Thus it is clear that the word "law" in Art.
13(1) does not include any law in the nature of a constitutional provision, for
no such law remained after the repeal'in Art. 395.
Then comes the second part of Art. 13, which
says that State shall not make any law which takes away or abridges the rights
conferred by this Part and any law made in contravention of this clause shall,
to the extent of the contravention, be void". The third part defines the
word "law" for the purpose of Art. 13; the definition is inclusive
and not exhaustive. It is because of the definition in cl. (3-) of Art. 13
being inclusive that it is urged that the word "law" in Art. 13 (2)
includes an amendment of the Constitution also. Now we see no reason why if the
word "law" in Art. 13(1) relating to past laws does not include any
constitutional provision the word "law" in cl. (2) would take in an
amendment of the Constitution, for it would be reasonable to the word
"law"'in Art. 13(2) includes an amendment of the 13. But apart from
this consideration, we are of opinion that the word "law" in Art
13(2) could never have been intended to take in an amendment of the
Constitution. What Art. 13(2) means is that a law made under the constitutional
provisions would, be tested on the anvil of Part III and if it takes away or
abridges rights conferred by Part III it would be void to the extent of the
contraventions. There are many Articles in the Constitution, which directly for
making law in addition to Articles 245, 246, 248, etc. and the three Lists
and-Aft.
13(2) (1) [1952] S.C.R. 89.
(2) [1965] 1 S.C.R 933.
840 prohibits the State from making any law
under these provisions. We see no difficulty in the circumstances in holding
that Art. 13 (2) when it talks of the State making any law, refers to the law
made under the provisions contained in Ch. I of Part XI of the Constitution
beginning with Art. 245 and also other provisions already referred to earlier.
Article 246 provides that Parliament may make laws for the whole or any part of
the territory of India and the legislature of a State may make laws for the
whole or any part of the State. Article 246(1) gives exclusive power to
Parliament to make laws with respect to subjects enumerated in List 1. Article
246(3) gives exclusive power to State legislatures to make laws with respect to
List II. Article 248(1) gives exclusive power to Parliament to make laws with
respect to any matter not enumerated in the Concurrent List or the State List.
We are referring to these provisions merely to show that the various provisions
in Chapter I of Part XI provide for making laws,and these laws are all laws
which are made under the legislative power conferred on Parliament or on State
legislatures under the Constitution.
Therefore when in Art. 13( ) it is said that
the State shall not make any law (State there including Parliament and
legislature of each State), its meaning could only take in laws made by
Parliament and State legislatures under the powers conferred under Chapter I of
Part XI. and also other provisions already referred to earlier. We have already
held that the power to amend the Constitution is to be found in Art. 368 along
with the procedure and that such power is not to be found in Art. 248 read item
97 of List I.
Therefore an amendment of the Constitution is
not an ordinary law made under the powers conferred under Chapter I of Part XI
of the Constitution and cannot be subject to Art.
13(2) where the word "law" must be
read as meaning law made under the ordinary legislative power. We have already
referred to a large number of Articles where Parliament is given the power to
make law with respect to those Articles.
So far as this power of Parliament is
concerned it is ordinary legislative power and it will certainly be subject to
Art. 13 (2). But there can in our opinion be no doubt that when Art. 13(2)
prohibits the State from making any law which takes away or abridges rights
conferred by Part III, it is only referring to ordinary legislative power
conferred on Parliament and legislatures of States and cannot halve any
reference to the constituent power for amendment of the Constitution contained
in Art. 368.
We have already pointed out that there are no
implied limitative on the power to amend under Art. 368 and it is open to
Parliament under that Article to amend any part of the Constitution, including
Part M. It is worth remembering that a whole Part XX is devoted by the
Constitution-makers to the subject of 841 amendment of the Constitution. If it
was their intention that Part III of the Constitution will not be liable to
amendment by way of abridgement or abrogation under the amending power
contained in Art. 368 we see no reason why an express provision to that effect
was not made in Art. 368.
We cannot see what prevented the Constituent
Assembly from making that clear by an express provision in Art. 368. It is
however said that it was not necessary to say so in Art.
368, because the provision was already made
in Art. 13(2).
We are unable to accept this contention, for
we have no doubt that Art. 13(2), when it refers to making of laws is only
referring to the ordinary legislative power and not to the constituent power
which results in amendment of the Constitution. In any case it seems to us
somewhat contradictory that in Art. 368 power should have been given to amend
any provision of the Constitution without any limitations but indirectly that
power is limited by using words of doubtful import in Art. 13(2). It is
remarkable that in Art. 13(2) there is no express provision that amendment of
the Constitution, under Art. 368, would be subject thereto. It seems strange
indeed that no express provision was made in Part XX in this matter and even in
Art. 13(2) no express provision is made to this effect, and in both places the
matter is left in a state of uncertainty.
It is also remarkable that in Art. 368 the
word "law", which we find so often used in so many Articles of the
Constitution is conspicuously avoided, and it is specifically provided that
after the procedure has been gone through the Constitution shall stand amended
in accordance with the terms of the Bill. This language of Art. 368 is very
significant and clearly makes a distinction between a constitutional Amendment
and an ordinary law passed as an Amending Act. The validity of a law has to be
determined at the time when the Bill actually matures into an Act and not at
the stage while it is still a Bill. The provision in Art. 368 has the effect
that when a Bill amending the Constitution receives the assent of the
President, the Constitution stands amended in accordance with the terms of the
Bill. The Constitution thus stands amended in terms of the Bill if the Bill has
been introduced, passed and assented to by the President in accordance with the
procedure laid down in Art. 368 and not as a result of the Bill becoming an
Amendment Act introducing amendment in the Constitution. The provision that the
Constitution shall stand amended in terms of the Bill was thus clearly intended
to indicate that the amendment of the Constitution is not dependent on the Bill
being treated as a law or an Act duly passed by Parliament. Thus it is clear
that by indicating that the Constitution is to stand amended in accordance with
the terms of the Bill, Art. 368 clearly envisages that the power of amendment
of the Constitution stands on an entirely different footing from an ordinary
law made by Parliament in exercise of its legislative power.
842 If We keep in mind this difference,
between constitutional amendment or constitutional law and an ordinary amending
Act or law, it should not be difficult to hold that when Art 13 (2), speaks of
the St-ate making a law, it is referring to ordinary law made under the powers
conferred by Art. 245 etc read with various Lists and various provisions of the
Constitution where express provision to that effect has been made and is not
referring to the amendment of the Constitution which is made under the
'constituent power.
Once it is held that the power to amend is
found in Art. 368 and is not to be found in Art. 248 read with item 97 of List
I, it must follow that the power to amend the Constitution under Art. 368 is a
different power (namely, constituent power) and when Art. 13 (2) speaks of
making 'law, it can only refer to making ordinary law, particularly when we
compare the words of Art. 13 (2) (namely, the State shall not make any law) and
the words of Arts. 245, 248, and 250 (which all speak of Parliament making law,
Statelegislatures making law, and so on).
Lastly, as the power to amend is in Art. 368
and on the words, as they stand in that Article, that power is unfettered and
includes the power to amend Part III, it is strange that that power should be
limited by putting an interpretation on the word "law" in Art. 13(2),
which would include constitutional law also. There is nothing to suggest this
even in the inclusive definition of the words "law" and "laws in
force" in Art. 13(3). Besides, it is conceded on behalf of the petitioners
that Art. 368 gives power to amend Part 111, but that power is only to amend
one way, namely, towards enlargement of the rights contained therein, and not
the other way, namely, for, abridging or taking away the rights contained
therein. W.-, must say that it would require a very clear provision in the Constitution
to read the power to amend the Constitution relating to Part III in this
manner. We cannot find that clear provision in Art. 1 3 (2). We repeat that
when the Constituent Assembly was taking the trouble of providing a whole Part
for amendment of the Constitution and when the words in Art. 368 clearly give
the power to amend the Constitution and are subject to no implied limitations
and contain no express limitations, it is strange indeed that it should have
omitted to provide in that very Article that Part III is not liable to
amendment thereunder. In any case if the power of amendment conferred by the
words of Art. 368 is unfettered, we must avoid any inconsistency between that
power and the provision contained in Art. 13 (2). We avoid that in keeping with
the unfettered power in Art. 368 by reading the word "law" in Art. 13
(2) as meaning law passed under: ordinary legislative power and thus not
including an amendment of the Constitution therein. The words in Art.II (2) are
in our opinion not specific and clear' enough to take in 843 the power of
amendment under Art. 368 and must be confined only to the power of ordinary
law-making contained in Arts.
245 etc., and other provisions of the
Constitution read with various Lists. We have therefore no hesitation in
agreeing with the view taken in Sankari Prasad's case(1) which was upheld by
the majority in Sajjan Singh's case(2).
The next argument is that action under the
proviso to Art.
368 is necessary as the Seventeenth Amendment
affects the power of the High Court contained in Art. 226. It is said that by
including various Acts in the Ninth Schedule and making them immune from
challenge under the provisions contained in Part III, the power of the High
Court under Art. 226 is affected inasmuch as the High Court cannot strike down
any of the Acts included in the Ninth Schedule on the ground that they take
away or abridge the rights conferred by Part III. So it is said that there has
been a change in Art. 226 and it was necessary that the Seventeenth Amendment
should have been ratified by more than half the States under the proviso. A
similar argument was raised in Sankari Prasad's case(1) and was turned down
unanimously.
The same argument was again raised in Sajjan
Singh's case(2) and was also turned down. Now ratification is required under
the proviso if the amendment seeks to make any change in various provisions
mentioned therein and one such provision is Art. 226. The question therefore is
whether the Seventeenth Amendment makes any change in Art. 226 and whether this
change has to be a direct change in the words of Art. 226 or whether merely
because there may be some effect by the Seventeenth Amendment on the, content
of the power in Art. 226 it will amount to change in Art. 226. We are of
opinion that when the proviso lays down that there must be ratification when
there is any change in the entrenched provisions, including Art. 226, it means
that there must be actual change in the terms of the provision concerned. If
there is no actual change directly in the entrenched provision, no ratification
is required, even if any amendment of any other provision of the Constitution
may have some effect indirectly on the entrenched provisions mentioned in the
proviso. But it is urged that there may be such a change in some other
provision as would seriously affect an entrenched provision, and in such a case
ratification should be necessary. This argument was also dealt with 'in the
majority judgment in Sajjan Singh's case(2) where the doctrine of pith and
substance was applied and it was held that where the amendment in any other
Article so affects the entrenched Article as to amount to an amendment therein,
then ratification may be necessary, even though the entrenched Article may not
be directly touched.
Perhaps the use of the doctrine of pith and
substance (1) [1952] S. C. R. 89.
(2) [1965] 1 S.C.P. 933.
844 in such a case is not quite apt. But what
was meant in Sajjan Singh's case(1) was that if there is such an amendment of
an unentrenched Article that it will directly affect an entrenched Article and
necessitate a change therein, then recourse must be had to ratification under
the proviso. We may illustrate this by two examples. Article 226 lays down
inter alia that the High Court shall have power to issue writs for the
enforcement of any of the rights conferred by Part III and for any other
purpose. Now assume that Part III is completely deleted by amendment of the
Constitution. If that takes place, it will necessitate an amendment of Art. 226
also and deletion therefrom of the words "for the enforcement of any of
the rights conferred by Part III". We have no doubt that if such a
contingency ever happens and Part III is completely deleted, Parliament will
amend Art. 226 also and that will necessitate ratification under the proviso.
But suppose Parliament merely deletes Part III and does not make the necessary
consequential amendment in Art. 226, it can then be said that deletion of Part
III necessitates change in Art. 226 also, and therefore in such a case ratification
is necessary, even though Parliament may not have in fact provided for
amendment of Art 226.
Take another example. Article 54 is an
entrenched Article and provides for the election of the President. So is Art.
55 which provides for the manner of election.
Article 52 which lays down that there shall be a President is on the other hand
not an entrenched Article. It is said that Art.
52 may be altered and something else may be
substituted in its place and that would not require ratification in terms as
Art. 52 is not among the entrenched Articles. But we are of opinion that if
Parliament amends Art. 52, it is bound to make consequential amendments in
Arts. 54 and 55 which deal with the election of the President and the manner
thereof and if it is so the entire amendment must be submitted for
ratification. But suppose Parliament merely amends Art. 52 and makes no change
in Arts. 54 and 55 (a supposition which is impossible to visualise). In that
case it would in our opinion be right to hold that Art. 52 could not be altered
by abolition of the office of the President without necessitating a change in
Arts. 54 and 55 and in such a case if Art. 52 alone is altered by Parliament,
to abolish the office of President, it will require ratification.
These two examples will show where alteration
or deletion of an unentrenched Article would necessitate amendment of an
entrenched Article, and in such a case if Parliament takes the incredible
course of amending only the unentrenched Article and not amending the entrenched
Article, courts can say that ratifi(1) [1965] 1 S.C.R. 933.
845 cation is necessary even for amending the
unentrenched Article, for it directly necessitates, a change in an entrenched
Article. But short of that we are of opinion that merely because there is some
effect indirectly on an entrenched Article by amendment of an unentrenched
Article it is not necessary that there should be ratification in such
circumstances also.
Besides, let us consider what would happen if
the argument on behalf of the petitioners is accepted that ratification is
necessary whenever there is even indirect effect on an entrenched Article by
amending an unentrenched Article.
Take the case of Art. 226 itself.. It gives
power to the High Court not only to issue writs for the enforcement of
fundamental rights but to issue them for any other purpose.
Writs have thus been issued by High Courts
for enforcing other rights conferred by ordinary laws as well as under other
provisions of the Constitution, like Arts. 301 and 311. On this argument if any
change is made in Arts. 301 and 311 there is bound to be an effect on Art. 216
and therefore ratification would be necessary, even though both Arts. 301 and
311 are not entrenched in the proviso.
Further, take an ordinary law which confers
certain rights and it is amended and those rights are taken away. Article 226
would be clearly affected. Before the amendment those rights may be enforced
through Art. 226 while after the amendment the rights having disappeared there
can be no enforcement thereof. Therefore, on this argument even if there is
amendment of ordinary law there would be an effect on Art. 226 and it must
therefore be amended every time even when ordinary law is changed and the
entire procedure under Art. 368 must be gone through including ratification
under the proviso. It is however said that when ordinary law is amended, rights
disappear and therefore there is no question of enforcement thereof; if that is
correct with respect to ordinary law, it is in our opinion equally correct with
respect to the amendment of an unentrenched provision of the Constitution. The
answer given in Sankari Prasad's case(1) to this argument was that Art. 226
remained just the same as it was before, and only a certain class of cases had
been excluded from the purview of Part III and the courts could no longer
interfere, not because their powers were curtailed in any manner or to any
extent, but because there would be no occasion thereafter for the exercise of
their power in such cases. We respectfully agree with these observations and
are of opinion that merely because there is some indirect effect on Art. 226 it
was not necessary that the Seventeenth Amendment should have been ratified by
more than one half of the States. It is only in the extreme case, the examples
of which we have given above, that an amendment of an unentrenched Article
without amendment of entrenched Article (1) [1952] S.C.R. 89.
846 might be had for want of ratification,
and this is what was intendedby the majority judgment in Sajjan Singh's
case(1), when it applied the doctrine of pith and substance in these
circumstances. The argument that ratification is necessary as Art. 226 is
indirectly affected has therefore no force and must be rejected. This is
equally true with respect to the power of this Court under Arts. 132 and 136.
Then it is urged that Art. 245 is enlarged by
the Seventeenth Amendment inasmuch as State legislatures and Parliament were
freed from the control of Part III in the matter of certain laws affecting, for
example. ryotwari lands, and therefore as Art. 245 is an entrenched Article
there should have been ratification under the proviso. This argument in our
opinion is of the same type as the argument with respect to the effect on Art.
226 and our answer is the same, namely, that there is no direct effect on Art.
245 by the amendment and the indirect effect, if.-any, does not require that
there should have been ratification in the present case.
It is then urged that ratification is
necessary as Art. 31-B deals with State legislation and in any case Parliament
cannot make, any law with respect to Acts which were put in the Ninth Schedule
and therefore Parliament could not amend the Constitution in the manner in
which it was done by making additions in the Ninth Schedule, both for want of
ratification and for want of legislative competence. The answer to this
argument was given in Sahkari Prasad's case(2) and it was observed there that"Article
31-A and 31-B really seek to save a certain class of laws and certain specified
laws already passed from the combined operation of Art. 13 read with other
relevant Articles of Part III. The new Articles being thus essentially
amendments of the Constitution, Parliament had the power of enacting them. That
laws thus saved relate to matters covered by List II does not in any way affect
the position. It was said that Parliament could not validate a law which it had
no power to enact. The proposition holds good where. the validity of the
impugned provision turns on whether the subject matter, falls within or without
the jurisdiction of the legislature which passed it.. But to make a law which
contravenes the Constitution, constitutionally valid is a matter of
constitutional amendment and as such it falls within the exclusive power of
Parliament." (1) [1965] 1 S.C.R. 933.
(2) [1952] S.C.R. 89.
847 We respectfully agree with these
observations. They succinctly put the legal and constitutional position with
respect to the 'validity of Arts, 3 1 A and 3 1 B. It seems to us that Art. 3 1
B in particular is a legislative drafting device which compendiously puts in
one place amendments which would otherwise have been added to the Constitution
under various Articles in Part III. The laws in the Ninth Schedule have by the
device of Art. 3 1 B been excepted from the various provisions in Part ]III,
which affected them and this exception could only be made by Parliament. The
infirmity in the Arts put in the Ninth Schedule was apprehended to be a
constitutional infirmity on the ground that those laws might take away or
abridge rights conferred by Part HI. Such a constitutional infirmity could not
be cured by State legislatures in any way and could only be cured by Parliament
by constitutional amendment. What Parliament in fact did by including various
Acts in the Ninth Schedule read with Art. 3 1 B was to amend the various
provisions in Part III, which affected these Acts by making them an exception
to those provisions in Part III. This could only be done by Parliament under
the constituent power it had under Art. 368 and there was no question of the
application of the proviso in such a case, for Parliament was amending Part III
only with respect to these laws. The laws had already been passed by State
legislatures and it was their constitutional infirmity, if any, which was being
cured by the device adopted in Art. 3 1 B read with the Ninth Schedule, the
amendment 'being only of the relevant provisions of Part III which was
compendiously put in one place in Art. 3 1 B. Parliament could alone do it
under Art. 368 and there was no necessity for any ratification under the
proviso, for amendment of Part III is not entrenched in the proviso.
Nor is there any force in the argument that
Parliament could' not validate those laws by curing the constitutional
infirmity because they dealt with land which is in List 11 of the Seventh
Schedule to the Constitution over which State Legislatures have exclusive
legislative power. The laws had already been passed by State legislatures under
their exclusive powers; what has been done by the Seventeenth Amendment is to
cure the constitutional' infirmity, if any, in these laws in relation to Part
III. That could only be done by Parliament and in so doing Parliament was not
encroaching on the exclusive legislative power of the State.
The States had already passed the laws and
all that was done by the Seventeenth Amendment was to cure any constitutional
infirmity in the laws by including them in the Ninth Schedule read with Art.
31-B. We must therefore reject the argument that the Seventeenth Amendment
required ratification because laws put in the Ninth Schedule were State law-,.
We must equally reject the argument that as these laws dealt with land, which
is in the848 exclusive legislative power of State legislature, Parliament could
not cure the constitutional infirmity, if any, in these laws by putting them in
the Ninth Schedule.
We now come to what may be called the
argument of fear. It is urged that if Art. 368 confers complete power to amend
each and every provision of the Constitution as we have held that it
does-frightful consequences will follow on such an interpretation. If
Parliament is clothed with such a power to amend the Constitution it may
proceed to do away with fundamental rights altogether, it may abolish elected
legislatures, it may change the present form of Government, it may do away with
the federal structure and create a unitary state instead, and so on. It is
therefore argued that we should give a limited interpretation to the power of
amendment contained in Art. 368, as otherwise we shall be giving power to
Parliament to destroy the Constitution itself.
This argument is really a political argument
and cannot be taken into account in interpreting Art. 368 when its meaning to
our mind is clear. But as the argument was urged with a good deal of force on
behalf of the petitioners and was met with equal force on behalf of the Union
and the States, we propose to deal with it briefly. Now, if this argument means
that Parliament may abuse its power of amendment conferred by Art. 368, all
that need be said in reply is that mere possibility of abuse cannot result in
courts withholding the power if the Constitution grants it. It is well-settled
so far as ordinary laws are concerned that mere possibility of abuse will not
induce courts to hold that the power is not there, if the law is valid and its
terms clearly confer the power. The same principle in our opinion applies to
the Constitution. If the Constitution gives a certain power and its terms are
clear, there is no reason why that power should be withheld simply because of
possibility of abuse. If we may say so, possibility of abuse of any power
granted to any authority is always there;
and if possibility of abuse is a reason for
withholding the power, no power whatever can ever be conferred on any
authority, be it "executive, legislative or even judicial.
Therefore, the so-called fear of frightful
consequences, which has been urged on behalf of the Petitioners (if we hold, as
we do, that the power to amend the Constitution is unfettered by any implied
limitations), is no ground for withholding the power, for we have no reason to
suppose that Parliament on whom such power is ,conferred will abuse it.
Further even if it abuses the power of constitutional
amendment under Art. 368 the check in such circumstances is not in courts but
is in the people who elect members of Parliament. The argument for giving a
limited 849 meaning to Art. 368 because of possibility of abuse must therefore
be rejected.
The other aspect of this argument of fear is
that we should not make the Constitution too flexible so that it may be open to
the requisite majority with the requisite ratification to make changes too
frequently in the Constitution. It is said that the Constitution is an organic
document for the governance of the country and it is expected to endure and
give stability to the institution which it provides. That is undoubtedly so and
this is. very true of a written federal Constitution. But a perusal of.
various Constitutions of the world shows that
there are usually provisions for amendment of the Constitution in the
Constitution itself. This power to amend a Constitution may be rigid or
flexible in varying degrees. Jurists have felt that where the power to amend
the Constitution is made too rigid and the people outgrow a particular
Constitution and feel that it should be amended but cannot do so because of the
rigidity of the Constitution, they break the Constitution, and this breaking is
more often than not by violent revolution. It is admitted by even those writers
on the United States Constitution who are of the view that there are certain
basic features which cannot be amended and who would thus make the U. S.
Constitution even more rigid' than it is; that howsoever rigid the Constitution
may be its rigidity will not stop the people from breaking it if they have
outgrown it and this breaking is, generally speaking, by violent revolution.
So, making our Constitution rigid by putting the interpretation which the
petitioners want us to put on it will not stop the frightfulness which is
conjured up before us on behalf of the petitioners. If anything, an
interpretation which will make our Constitution rigid in the manner in which
the petitioner want the amending power in Art. 368 to be interpreted will make
a violent revolution, followed by frightfulness of which the petitioners are
afraid, a nearer possibility than an interpretation which will make it
flexible.
It is clear that our Constitution-makers
wanted to avoid' making the Constitution too rigid. It is equally clear that
they did not want to make an amendment of the Constitution too easy. They
preferred an intermediate course which would make,the Constitution flexible and
would still not allow it to be amended too easily. That is why Art. 368
provides for special majorities of the two Houses for the purpose of amendment
of the Constitution. Besides it also provides for ratification by more than
half the States in case of entrenched Provisions in the proviso. Subject to
these limitations, the Constitution has been, made moderately flexible to allow
any change when the people feel that change is necessary. The necessity for
special majorities 850 in each House separately and, the necessity for,
ratification by more than half the States in certain cases appear to us to be
sufficient safeguards to prevent too easy change in the Constitution without
making it too rigid. But it is said that, in the last sixteen Years, a large
number of amendments have been made to the constitution and that shows that the
power to amend is much too easy and should be restricted by judicial
interpretation. Now, judicial interpretation cannot restrict the power on the
basis of a political argument. It has to interpret the Constitution and finds
it on the basis of well-known,canons of construction,and on the terms of Art.
368 in particular. If on those terms it is clear we think it is-that power to
amend is subject to no limitations except those to be expressly found in the
Constitution, courts must give effect to that. The fact that 'm the last
sixteen years a large number of amendments could be made and have been made is
in our opinion due to the accident that one party has been returned by electors
in sufficient strength to be able to command the special majorities which are
required under Art.
368, not only at the Centre but also in all
the Stites. It' is because of this circumstance that we have had so many
amendments in the course of the last sixteen years. But that in our opinion is
no ground for limiting the clear words of Art. 368.
The power of amendment contained in a written
federal Constitution is a safety valve which to a large extent provides for
stable growth and makes violent revolution more or less unnecessary. It has been
said by text-book writers that the power of amendment, though it allows for
change, also makes a Constitution long lived and stable and serves the needs of
the people from time to time. If this power to amend is made too rigid it loses
its value as a safety valve. The more rigid a Constitution the more likely it
is that people will outgrow it and throw it over-board violently. On the other
hand, if the Constitution is flexible (though it may not be made too easy to
modify it) the power of amendment provides for stability of the Constitution
itself and for ordered progress of the nation. If therefore there had to be a
choice between giving an interpretation-to Art. 368 which would make our
Constitution rigid and giving an interpretation which would make it flexible,
we would prefer to make it flexible, so that it may endure for a long period of
time and may, if necessary, be amended from time to time in accordance with the
progress in the ideas of the people for whom it is meant. But we feel that it
is not necessary to go to this extent, for that would be entering into the
field of politics. As we see the terms of Art. 368, we are clearly Df opinion
that the Constitutionmakers wanted to make our Constitution reasonably flexible
and ,.that the interpretation that we have given to Art. 368 is in 851
consonance with the terms thereof and the intention of those who made it. We
therefore reject the argument of fear altogether.
This brings us to the argument of stare
decisis raised on behalf of the Union of India and the States. The argument is
put thus. After the decision of the Patna High Court invalidating the Bihar
Land Reforms Act, 1950, Parliament passed the First Amendment to the
Constitution. That Amendment was challenged in this Court by a number of writ petitions
and was upheld in Sankari Prasad's case(-) in 1951. That case practically stood
unchallenged till Sajjan Singh's case(2) in 1964 after the Seventeenth
Amendment was passed. Thus in the course of these fifteen years or so a large
number of State Acts were passed on the basis of the First Amendment by which
in particular Arts. 31-A and 31-B were introduced in the Constitution. It is
said that though Sankari Prasad's case (1) has stood for less than 15 years
there have been so many laws dealing with agrarian reforms passed on the basis
of the First Amendment which was upheld by this Court that the short period for
which that case has stood should not standin the way of this Court acting an
the principle of, stare decisis. The reason for this is that an agrarian
revolution, has taken place all over the country after the First Amendment by
State laws passed on the faith of the decision of this Court in Sankari
Prasad's case(1). This agrarian revolution has led to millions of acres of land
having changed hands and millions of now titles having been created. So it is
urged that the unanimous decision in Sankari Prasad's case(2), which was
challenged when the Seventeenth Amendment was passed and was upheld by majority
in Sajjan Singh's case(2) should not now be disturbed as its disturbance would
create chaos in the country, particularly in the agrariansector which
constitutes the vast majority of the population in this country.
We are of opinion that there is force in this
argument .
Though the period for which Sankari Prasad's
case(1) has stood unchallenged is not long, the effects which have followed in,
the passing of State laws on the faith of that decision', are so overwhelming
that we should not disturb the decision in that case. It is not disputed that
millions of acres of land have changed hands and millions of new titles in
agricultural lands have been created and the State laws dealing with
Agricultural land which have been passed in the course of the last fifteen
years after the decision in Samkari Prasad's case(1) have brought about an
agrarian revolution. Agricultural population constitutes a vast majority of the
population in this country. In these circumstances it would in our opinion be
wrong to hold now that (1) [1952] S.C.R. 89.
(2) [1965] 1 S.C.R. 933.
852 Sankari Prasad's case (1) was not
correctly decided and thus disturb all that has been done during the last
fifteen years and create chaos into the lives of millions. of our countrymen
who have benefited by these laws relating, to agrarian reforms. We would in the
circumstances accept the argument on behalf of the Union of India and the
States that this is the fittest possible case in which the principle of stare
decisis should be applied. On this basis also, apart from our view that Sankari
Prasad's case (1) was in fact rightly decided, we would not interfere with that
decision now.
But it is urged that instead of following the
principle of stare decisis which would make die decision in Sankari Prasad's
case(1) good for all times., we should follow the doctrine of prospective
over-ruling, which has been evolved by some United States courts so that
everything that has been done up to now, including the Seventeenth Amendment
would be held good but in future it would not be open to Parliament to amend
Part III by taking away or abridging any of the rights conferred thereby and,
if the argument as to implied limitations on the power to amend is accepted,
further limit the power of Parliament to amend what may be called basic
features of the Constitution. We must say that we are not prepared to accept
the doctrine of prospective over-ruling. We do not know whether this doctrine
which it is urged should be applied to constitutional amendment would also be
applied to amendments of ordinary laws. We find it difficult to visualise what
would be the effect of this doctrine if it is applied to amendment of ordinary
laws. We have so far been following in this country the well-known doctrine
that courts declare law and that a declaration made by a court is the law of
the land and takes effect from the date the law came into force. We would on
principle be loath to change that well-known doctrine and supersede it by the
doctrine of prospective over-ruling. Further it seems to us that in view of the
provisions of Art. 13(2) it would be impossible to apply the doctrine of
prospective overruling in our country, particularly where a law infringes
fundamental rights. Article 13(2) lays down that all. laws taking away or
abridging fundamental rights would be void to the extent of contravention. It
has been held by this Court in Deep Chand v. The State of Uttar Pradesh (2)
that a law made after the Constitution came into force which infringes
fundamental rights is a stillborn law and that the prohibition contained in
Art. 13(2) went to the root of the State power of legislation and any-law made
in contravention of that provision was void ab initio. This case has been
followed in Mahendra Lal Jaini v. The State of Uttar Pradesh(3). In the face of
these (1) [1952] S.C.R. 89. (2) [1959] Supp. 2 S.C.R. 8.
(3) [1963] Supp. 1. S.C.R. 912.
853 decisions it is impossible to apply the
principle of prospective over-ruling in this country so far as ordinary laws
are concerned. Further, if the word "law" in Art.
13(2) includes an amendment of the
Constitution, the same principle will apply, for that amendment would be
stillborn if it infringes any fundamental rights contained in Part III. In
these circumstances, it would be impossible to apply the principle of prospective
over-ruling to constitutional amendments also. On the other hand, if the word
"law" in Art. 13(2) does not include an amendment of the
Constitution, then there is no necessity of applying the principle of
prospective over-ruling, for in that case unless some limitations on the power
of amendment of the Constitution are implied the amendment under Art. 368 would
not be liable to be tested under Art. 13(2). We are therefore unable to apply
the doctrine of prospective overruling in the circumstances. Further as we are
of opinion that this is the fittest possible case in which the principle of
stare decisis applies,we must uphold Sankari Prasad's case (1) for this reason
also.
Lastly we would refer to the following
observations in Sajjan Singh's case(2) (at pp. 947-48) with respect to overruling
earlier judgments of this Court and specially those which are unanimious like
Sankari Prasad's case(1):"It is true that the Constitution does not place
any restriction on our powers to review our earlier decisions or even to depart
from them and there can be no doubt that in matters relating to the decision of
constitutional points which have a significant impact on the fundamental rights
of citizens, we would be prepared to.' review our earlier decisions in the
interest of public good............. Even so, the normal principle that
"judgments pronounced by this Court would be final, cannot be ignored and
unless considerations of a substantial and compelling character make it
necessary to. . do so, we should be slow to doubt the correctness of previous
decisions.or to depart from them.
"It is universally recognised that in
regard to a large number of constitutional problems which are brought before
this Court for its decision, complex and difficult questions arise and on many
of such questions two views are possible. Therefore, if one view has been
taken. by this Court after mature deliberation, the fact that another Bench is
inclined to take a different-view may not justify the Court in reconsidering
the earlier decision or in departing from, it................ Even so, the
Court should be re(1) (1952] S.C.R. 89. (2) [1965] 1 S.C.R.
933.
p. CI/67-9 854 luctant to accede to the
suggestion that its earlier decisions should be light-heartedly reviewed and
departed from. In such a case the test should be: is it absolutely necessary
and essential that the question already decided should be reopened The answer
to this question would depend on the nature of the infirmity alleged in the
earlier decision, its impact on public good, and the validity and compelling
character of the considerations urged in support of the contrary view. If the
said decision has been followed in a large number of cases, that again is a
factor which must be taken into account." A similar view was taken in the
Keshav Mills Company Limited v. Commissioner of Income-tax,(1) where it was
observed that"...before a previous decision is pronounced to be plainly
erroneous, the Court must be satisfied with a fair amount of unanimity amongst
its members that a revision of the said view is fully justified." These
principles were applied in Sajjan Singh's case(2) and it was observed that if
Sankari Prasad's case(3) were to be overruled, "it would lead to the
inevitable consequence that the amendments made in the Constitution both in
1951 and 1955 would be rendered invalid and a large number of decisions dealing
with the validity of the Acts included in the Ninth Schedule which have been
pronounced by, different High Courts ever since the decision of this Court in
Sankari Prasad's case(3) was declared, would also be exposed. to serious
jeopardy." The majority in that case therefore was not in favour of
reviewing Sankari Prasad's case(".) even so in View of the argument raised
and the importance of the question it considered the arguments against that
decision and came to the conclusion its that that case was rightly decided We
may add that besides so many cases in the High Courts there have been a large
number of cases in this Court to which it is unnecessary to refer where on the
faith of various amendments made in the Constitution, particularly the First,
the Fourth and the Sixteenth, amending fundamental rights, this Court has
upheld the, validity of various Acts on the basis of these amendments. Further
we would be very reluctant to over-rule the unanimous decision in Sankari
Prasad's case.(3) or any other unanimous decision by the slender majority of
one in a larger Bench constituted for the purpose. We say this with great
respect and would hold that apart 'from the principle of stare decisis we
should not say that the (1) [1965] 2 S.C.R. 908.
(2) [1965] 1 S.C.R. 933 (3) [1952] S.C.R. 89
855 unanimous judgment in Sankari Prasad's case(,) was wrongly decided by such
a slender majority in this Special Bench.
We therefore hold that Sankari Prasad's
cases(1) was correctly decided and that the majority,in Sajjan Singh's case(2)
WAS Correct in following that decision. We would follow the decision in Sankari
Prasad's case(1) even now as in our opinion it was correctly decided.'
Following that decision we hold that the Seventeenth Amendment is good.
In view of this decision it is unnecessary to
refer to other arguments raised with respect to the two petitions challenging
the Mysore Land Reforms Act.
In our view therefore all the three petitions
should fail and we would dismiss them. In the circumstances we would pass no
order as to costs.
Hidayatulla. J In these three writ petitions,
the facts of which appear in the two judgment just delivered, the validity of the
Punjab Security of Land Tenures Act, 1953 and the Mysore Land Reforms Act,
1953, is principally involved. ' Since these Acts are protected by the
Constitution (Seventeenth Amendment) Act, 1964, the validity of the
constitutional amendment is also questioned.
Therefore, a much larger field must be
traversed because of the claim of the State that no part of the Constitution
from the Preamble to the Ninth Schedule, is beyond the provision for amendment
contained in Art. 368. The article, forms the Twentieth Part of the
Constitution and is said to be a code by itself in which reposes a sovereign
power, transcending anything elsewhere in the Constitution. The State submits
that (except as stated in the article) there are no limitations on the amending
power and denies that there are any implied restrictions. It claims, therefore,
that an amendment of the Constitution Or of any of its part can never be a
justiciable issue if the procedure for amendment has been duly followed. In
this claim no exception is madethe Preamble, the Fundamental Rights, the
guaranteed remedy to uphold them all of them severally and together are said to
be capable of being Partially or wholly abrogated by an amendment. Looked at
from, this Point of view the Seventeenth Amendment Act not only 'must be valid
but also beyond the Power of the courts to question. The petitioners, on the
other hand, contend that this is to deny the real importance and inviolability
of the Fundamental Rights which the Constitution itself, paramount even to Art.,
368 consideration.' before we can Acts are valid or not.
(1) [1952] S.C.R. 89. (2) [1965] 1 S.C.
R.933.
856 The same questions were before this Court
on two earlier occasions. They arose for the first time immediately after the
Constitution (First Amendment) Act, 1951 was adopted and became the subject of
a decision of this Court reported in Sri Sankari Prasad Singh Deo v. Union of
India(1). There Patanjali Sastri J. speaking for Harilal Kania C.J., Mukherjea,
Das and Chandrasekhara Aiyar, JJ.and himself upholds the First Amendment on the
grounds that the power conferred by Part XX is constituent, paramount and
sovereign and is, therefore, not subject to Art. 13(2) which prohibits the
making of ordinary laws tending to abridge or take away Fundamental Rights.The
questions were again before the Court in sajjan Singh c. State of Rajasthan(2)
when the Seventeenth Amendment was impugned. The authority of Sankari Prasad's
case(1) was the ministry ofof the argument in support of the validity of the
new amendment. This time the Court was not unanimous although the Court as aas
a whole did not strike down the Act. Three opinions weredelivered by
Gajendragadkar, C.J. on behalf of Wanchoo and Raghubar Dayal, JJ. and himself,
by Mudholkar, J. and by me. I found the reasoning in Sankari Prasad's case(1)
to be unacceptable, although for reasons which I shall give, I refrained from
expressing a final opinion. Mudholkar, J. in his opinion supported me with
additional and forceful reasons but he also did not express himself finally on
the broader question. I closed my opinion with the following observations :-"I
would require stronger reasons than those given in Sankari Prasad's case(1) to
make me accept the view that Fundamental Rights were not really fundamental but
were intended to be within the powers of amendment in common with the other
parts of the Constitution and without the concurrence of the States. No doubt
Art. 19 by clauses numbered 2 to 6 allows a curtailment of rights in the public
interest. Ibis shows that Part III is not static. It Visualises changes and
progress but at the same time it preserves the individual rights. There is
hardly any measure of reform which cannot be introduced reasonably, the
guarantee of individual liberty notwithstanding. Even the agrarian reforms
could have been partly carried out without Article 31-A and 31-B but they would
have cost more to the public exchequer. 'the rights of society are made
paramount and they ire placed above those of the individual.
This is as it should be. But restricting the
Fundamental Rights by resort to cls. 2 to 6 of Mt. 19 is (1) [1952] S.C.R. 89.
(2) [1965] 1 S.C.R. 933.
857 one thing and removing the rights from
the Constitution or debilitating them by an amendment is quite another. This is
the implication of Sankari Prasad's case(1). It is true that such things would
never be, but one is concerned to know if such a doing would be possible."
"The Constitution gives so many assurances in Part III that it would be
difficult to think that they were the playthings of a special majority. To hold
this would prima facie that the most solemn parts of our Constitution stand on
the same footing as any other provision and even on a less firm ground than one
on which the articles mentioned in the proviso stand. The anomaly that Art. 226
should be somewhat protected but not Art. 32 must give us pause. Article 32
does not erect a shield against private conduct but against state conduct
including the legislatures (See Art. 12). Can the legislature take away this
shield ? Perhaps by adopting a liberal construction of Art. 368 one can say
that.
But I am not inclined to play a grammarian's
role. As at present advised I can only say that the power to make amendments
ought not ordinarily to be a means of escape from absolute constitutional
restrictions." My opposition (lest one misunderstands its veridical character)
appears to be cautious and even timid but this was because it was attended by
an uneasy feeling that I might have missed some immanent truth beyond what was
said in Sankari Prasad's case(1). The arguments then were extremely brief.
After hearing full arguments in thiscase, which have not added to the reasoning
of the earlier cases, I am not satisfied that the reasons are cogent enough for
me to accept them. I say it with respect that I felt then, as I do so even more
strongly now, that in the two earlier cases, the result was reached by a
mechanical juris prudence in which harmonious construction was taken to mean
that unless Art. 368 itself made an exception the existence of any other
provision indicative of an implied limitation on the amending power, could not
be considered. This was really to refuse to consider any argument which did not
square with the a priori view of the omnicompetence of Art. 368. Such reasoning
appears to me to be a kind of doctrinaire conceptualism based on an and textual
approach supplemented by one concept that an amendment of the Constitution is
not an exercise of legislative (1) [1952] S.C.R. 89.
858 power but of constituent Dower and,
therefore, an amendment of the Constitution is not law at all as contemplated
by Art. 13(2). I. am reminded of the. words of. Justice Holmes that "we
,must thinkthings and not words". The true principle is that if there are
two provisions in the Constitution which seem to be hostile, juridical
hermeneutics requires the Court to interpret them by combining them and not by
destroying one with the aid of the other. No part in a Constitution is superior
to another part unless the Constitution itself says so and there is no
accession 'of strength to any provision by calling it a code. Portalis, the
great. French Jurist .(who helped in the making of the Code Napole on) supplied
the correct principle when he said that it is the context of the legal
provisions which serves to illustrate the meaning. of the different parts, so
that among them and between them there should be correspondence and harmony.
We have two provisions to reconcile. Article
368 which says that the Constitution may be amended by, following this and
this. procedure, and Art. 13(2) which says, the State shall not make any law
which takes away or abridges the rights conferred by Part III and that any law
made in contravention of the clause shall, to the extent of the contravention, be
void. The question, therefore, is : doesthis create any limitation upon the
amending process ? On the answer to this question depends the solution of all
the problems in this case.
It is an error to view our Constitution as if
it were a mere organisational document by which the people established the
atructure and the mechanism of their Government. Our Constitution is intended
to be much more because it aims at being a social document In which the
relationship of society to the indiVidual and of Government to both and the
rights of the minorities and the backward classes are clearly laid down. This
social document is headed by a Preamble* which epitomizes the principles on
which the Government is intended to function and these principles are later expanded
into Fundamental Rights in Part III and the Directive Principles of Policy in
Part TV. The former 'are protected but the latter are not. The former represent
the "PREAMBLE WE THE PEOPLE OF INDIA having solemnly Resolved to
.constitute India into a SOVEREIGN DEMOCRATIC REPUBLIC and to secure all Its
citizens:
JUSTICE, social, economic and political;
EQUALITY of status and of opportunity; and to
promote among them.all FRATERNITY assuring the, dignity of the individual
and.the unity of Nation:
IN OUR CONSTITUENT ASSEMBLY this twenty-sixth
day of
November,1949,do HEREBY ADOPT,ENACT AND GIVE
TO OURSELVES
THIS CONSTffUTION." 859 limits of State
action and the latter are the obligations and the duties of the Government as a
good and social Government.
Why was it necessary to have the Fundamental
Rights at all and make them justiciable ? As we seem to be forgetting our own
history so soon let me say that the answer lies there the Nationalist Movement
and the birth of the Indian National Congm in 1885 were the direct result of
the discriminatory treatment of the Indians in their own country. The demand
for the guarantee of Fundamental Rights had unfortunately to be made. then to a
foreign ruler and it appeared in the Constitution of India Bill framed by the Indian
National Congress ten years later. All that is valuable to an Individual in
civilized society, including free speech, imprisonment only by a competent
authority, free law education, etc. were claimed therein. Resolutions of the
Congress since then reiterated this demand and the securing of Fundamental
Rights in any future Constitution became one of the articles of faith. To cut
the narration short, the main steps may only be mentioned. Mrs. Besant's
Commonwealth of India Bill 1925 with its seven fundamental rights (the
precursor of Art. 19), the Madras Congress Resolution of 1927--"a
constitution on the basis of declaration of rights"-the Nehru Report--it
is obviour, that our first care should be to have the Fundamental Rights
guaranteed in a manner which will not permit their withdrawal in any
circumstancees--, the draft article in the Nehru Constitution "No person
shall be deprived of his liberty, nor shall his dwelling or property be
entered, requisitioned or confiscated save in accordance with law"-, the
Independence Resolution of 26th January, 1930--We believe that it is the
inalienable right of the Indian people, as of any other people, to have freedom
and to enjoy the fruits of their toil and have the necessities of life, so that
they may have full opportunities of growth" the Karachi Resolution on
Fundamental Rights, Economic and Social Change (1931), the Sapru Report (1945)
which for the first time distinguished between justiciable and non,justiciable
rights, the Suggestion of the Cabinet Mission for the constitution of an
Advisory Committee on Fundamental and Minority Rights, and, lastly the
Committee on Fundamental Rights of the Constituent Assembly, are just a few of
the steps to be remembered. The Fundamental Rights and the Directive Principles
were the result.
Fundamental laws are needed to make a
Government of laws and not of men and the Directive Principles are needed to
lay down the objectives of a good Government. Our Constitution was not the
cause but the result of political and personal freedom". Since Dicey had
said that "the proclamation . in a Constitution or Charter of the right to
personal freedom, or indeed of any other right, gives of itself but slight
security that the right has more than a 860 nominal existence",(1) provision
had to be made for guaranteeing them andto make them justiciable and
enforceable. This result is reachedby means of Arts. 12, 13, 32, 136, 141, 144
and 226. The The High Courts and finally this Court have been made the Judges
of whether any legislative or executive action on the part oft the State
considered as comprehensively as is possible, offends the Fundamental Rights
and Art. 13(2) declares that legislation which so offends is to be deemed to be
void. It is thus that Parliament cannot today abridge or take away a single
Fundamental Right even by a 'unanimous vote in both the Chambers. But on the
argument of the State it has only 'to change the title of the same Act to an
Amendment of the Constitution Act and then a majority of the total strength and
a 2/3rds majority of the members present and voting in each House may remove
not only any of the Fundamental Rights, but the whole Chapter giving them. And
this is said to be possible because of Art. 368 and its general language which,
it is claimed, makes no exception in its text and, therefore, no exception can
be implied. It is obvious that if an Act amending the Constitution istreated as
a law it must also be subject to the provisions of Art. 13(2). Since the
definition of the word 'law', makes no exception a strenuous eeffort is made on
the basis of argument and authority to establish that a constituent power does
not result in a law in the ordinary sense. Distinction is thus made between
laws made ordinarily that is to say, from day to day by ordinary majority and
laws made occasionally for the amendment of the Constitution by a slightly
enhanced majority. In our Constitution this distinction is not valid in the eye
of Art. 13(2).
It is not essential,, of course, that a
difference must always exist in the procedure for the exercise of constituent
and ordinary, legislative power. One has not to go far to find the example of a
country in which constitutional law as such may be made by the same agency
which makes ordinary laws. The most outstanding, example is that of England
about which de Tocqueville observed.
"the Parliament has an acknowledged
right to modify the Constitution; as, therefore, the Constitution may undergo
perpetual changes, it does not in reality exist; the Parliament is at once a
legislative and a constituent assembly:"(2) of course, the dictum of de
Tocqueville that the English Constitution "elle n'existe point" (it
does not exist) is far from accu(1)Dicey: "Law of the Constitution"
10th Edn. p. 207.
(2)Introduction to the Study of the Law of
the Constitution A.V. Dicey Tenth Edn p. 88 quoting from OEuvres completes
(14th ed.,1864) (Democratie en Amerique), pp. 166, 167.
861 rate. There is a vast body of
constitutional laws in England which is written and statutory but it is not all
found in one place and arranged as a written Constitution usually is. The Act
of Settlement (1701), the Act of Union with Scotland (1707), the Act of Union
with Ireland (1800) the Parliament Act (1911) the Representation of the Peoples
Acts of 1832, 1867, 1884, 1918, 1928 and 1948, the Ballot Act (1872), the
Judicature Acts 1873, 1875 and 1925, the Incitement to Disaffection Act (1934),
His Majesty's Declaration of Abdication Act (1936), the Regency Act (1937) and
the various Acts setting up different ministries are examples of what will pass
for constitutional law under our system(1). The Bill of Rights (1689) lays down
the fundamental rule in England that taxation may not be levied without the
consent of Parliament which in our Constitution has its counterpart in Art.
265. In our Constitution also the laws relating to delimitation of
constituencies or allotment of seats to such constituencies made or purporting
to be made under Art. 327 or Art. 328, by reason of the exclusion of the powers
of the courts to question them, are rendered constitutional instruments. Other
examples of constitutions which, in addition to constitution proper, contain
certain ordinary legislation, having constitutional qualities, also exist. (2)
What then is the real distinction between ordinary law and the law made in the
exercise of constituent power? I would say under the scheme of our Constitution
none at all. This distinction has been attempted to be worked out by several
authors. It is not necessary to quote them. Taking the results obtained by
Willoughby(3) it may be said that the fact that a Constitution is written as a
Constitution is no distinction because in Britain constitutional law is of both
kinds and both parts coexist. The test that the Constitution requires a different
kind of procedure for amendment, also fails because in Britain Parliament by a
simple majority makes laws and also amends constitutional statutes. In our
Constitution too, in spite of the claim that Art. 368 is a code (whatever is
meant by the word ,code, here), Arts. 4, 11 and 169 show that the amendment of
the Constitution can be by the ordinary law making procedure. By this method
one of the legislative limbs in a State can be removed or created. 'This
destroys at one stroke the claim that Art. 368 is a code arid also that any
special method of amendment of the Constitution is fundamentally necessary.
(1) The list is raken from K. C. Wheare's:
"The Statute of Westminster and Dominion Status" (4th Edn) p. 8.
Dicey and others give different list.
(2) See Constitutions of Austria, Honduras,
Nicaragua Peru, Spain and Sweden among others. The Constitution of Spain, in
particular is in several Instruments. The Constitution of Austria (A-t. 149)
makes special mention of these constitutional instruments.
(3) Tagore Law Lectures (1924) p. 83.
862 The next test that the courts must apply
the Constitution in preference to the ordinary law may also be rejected on the
ansalogy of the British practice. There, every statute has equal standing.
Therefore, the only difference can be said to arise from the fact
that.constitutional laws are generally amendable under a process which in
varying degrees, is more difficult or elaborate. This may give a distinct
character to the law of the Constitution but it does not serve to distinguish
it from the other laws of the land for purposes of Art. 13(2). Another
difference is that in the written constitutions the form and power of
Government alone are to be found and not rules of private law as is the case
with ordinary laws. But this is also not an invariable rule. The Ame
Constitution and our Constitution itself are outstanding examples There are
certain other differences of degree, such as that nary _legislation may be
tentative or temporary, more detailed or secondary, while the Constitution is
intended to be permanent, general and primary. Because it creates limitations
on the ordinary legislative power, constitutional law in a sense is fundamental
law, but if the legislative and constituent processes can become one, Ls there
any reason why the result should be regarded as law in the one case and not in
the other ? On the whole, therefore, as observed in the American Jurisprudence
"It should be noticed however that a statute and a constitution, though of
unequal dignity are both laws and each rests on the will of the
people........" A Constitution is law which is intended to be, for all
time and is difficult to change so that it may not be subject to "impulses
ofmajority" "temporary excitement and popular caprice or
passion"(2).
I agree with the authors cited before us that
the power of amendment must be possessed by the State. I do not take a narrow
view of the word "amendment" as including only minor changes within
the general framework. By an amendment new matter may be added, old matter
removed or altered. I alm concede that the reason for the amendment of the
Constitution is a political matter although I do not go as far as some Justice
of the Supreme court of the United States did in Coleman v. Miller(3) that the
whole process is "political in its entirely from submission until an
Amendment becomes part of the Constitution and is not subject to judicial
guidance, control or interference at any point." There are fundamental
differences between our Con(1) American Jurispruence Vol. II Section 3.
(2) Amendment is expressly called a
legislative process in the Constitutions of Colombia:, Costa Rica, Hungary,
Panama and Peru.. In Portugal the ordinary legislatures enjoy constituent
powers every 10 years.
(3) 3)7 U.S. 443 (83 L. Ed. 1385).
863 stitution and the Constitution of the
United States of America.. Indeed this: dictum of the four Justices based upon,
the case of Luther v. Borden(1) has lost some of its force after Baker v.
Carr(2) A Republic must, as says Story, (8) possess the means for altering and
improving the fabric of the Government so as, to promote the happiness and
safety of the people. The power is also needed to disarm opposition and prevent
factions over the Constitution. The power, however, is not intended to be used
for experiments or as an escape from restrictions against undue state action
enacted in the Constitution itself. Nor %'LS the power of amendment available
for the purpose of removing express or fmplied restrictions against the State.
Here I make a difference between Government
and State which I shall explain presently. As Willoughby(4) points out
constitutional law ordinarily limits Government but not the State because a
constitutional law is the creation of the State for its own purpose. But there
is nothing to prevent the State from limiting itself. The rights and duties of
the individual and the manner in which such rights are to be exercised and
enforced ;ire ordinarily to be found in the laws though some of the
Constitutions also fix them. It is now customary to have such rights guaranteed
in the Constitution. Peaslee,(5) writing in 1956 says that about 88% of the
national Constitutions contain clauses respecting individual liberty and fair
legal process; 83% respecting freedom of speech and the press; 82% respecting
property right; 80% respecting rights of assembly and association;
80% respecting rights of conscience and
religion; 79% respecting secrecy of correspondence and inviolability of domicile;
78% respecting education; 73% respecting equality 64% respecting right to
petition; 56% respecting labour; 51% respecting social security; 47% respecting
rights of movement within, and to and from the nation; 47% respecting health
and motherhood; and 35% respecting the nonretroactivity of laws. In some of the
Constitutions there is an attempt to put a restriction against the State
seeking to whittle down the rights conferred on the individual. Our
Constitution is the most outstanding example of this restriction which is to be
found in Art. 13(2). 'The State is no doubt legally supreme but in the
supremacy of its powers it may create, impediments on its own sovereignty.
Government is always bound by the
restrictions created in favour of fundamental Rights but the State may or may
not be. Amendment may be open to the State according to the procedure laid (1)
7 How. 1 (12 L. Ed. 58). (2) 369 U. S. 186 (7 L.
Ed. 2d 633).
(3) Commentaries on the Constittition of the
United States (1833) Vol. III pp 686-687.
(4) Tagore Law Lectures, p. 84.
(5) Constitutions of Nations, Vol. I (2nd
Edn.) p. 7.
863 stitution and the Constitution of the
United States of America.this: dicttan of the four Justices based upon, the
case of Luther v. Borden(1) has lost some of its force after Baker v. Carr(2).
A Republic must, as says Story,-(,,) ssess
the means for ai and:improving the 'fabric of tc Government so as, to promote
the happiness and safety, of the people. The power, is dw needed to disarm
opposition and prevent factions over theThe power, however, is not intended to
be used for experiments or as an escape from restrictions against undue state
action enacted in the Constitution itself. Nor is the power of amendment
available for the purpose of removing express or implied restrictions against
the State.
Here I make a difference between Government
and Statewhich I shall explain presently. As Willoughby(4) points out
wmtitutional law ordinarily limits Government but not the State because a
constitutional la,* is the creation of the State for its own pu, se. But there
is nothing to prevent the State from rpo limiting itself. The rights and duties
of the individual and the. manner in which such rights are to be exercised and
enforced are ordinarily to be found in the laws though some of the
Constitutions also fix them. It now customary to have such rights guaranteed in
the Constitution. Peaslee,(5) writing in 1956 says that about 88,Yo of the,
national Constitutions contain clauses respecting individual liberty and fair
legal process; 83% respecting freedom of speech and the press; 82% respecting
property right; 80% respecting rights of assembly and association; 80%
respecting rights of conscience and religion; 79% respecting secrecy of
correspondence and' inviolability of domicile; 78% respecting education; 73% respecting
equality; .64% respecting right to petition; 56% respecting labour; 51%
respecting social security; 47% respecting rights of movement within, and to
and from the nation; 47% respecting health and motherhood; and 35% respecting
the non-retroactivity of laws. In some of the Constitutions there is an attempt
to put a restriction Against the State seeking to whittle down the rights
conferred' on the 'individual. Our Constitution is the most outstanding
i6xample of this restriction Which is to be found in Art. 1.3(2). ,Tbe State is
no doubt legally supreme but in the supremacy of its powers it may creat-eimpediments
on its OI%M sovereignty. Govent is always bound by the restrictions created in
favour of Fundamental Rights but the State may or may not be. Amendment may be
open to the State according to the procedure lai(r (1)7 How. 1 (12 L. Ed. 58).
(2) 369 U. S. 186 (7 L. Ed.
2d 633).
(3) Commentaries on the Constitution of the
United, Sta:tes (1 833)'Vol. III PP, 686-687.
(4)Tagore Law Lectures, p. 84.
(5)Constitutions of Nations, Vol. I (2nd
Edn.) p. 7.
864 down by the Constitution. There is
nothing, however, to prevent the State from placing certain matters outside the
amending procedure('). Examples of this exist in several Constitutions of the
world : see Art. 5 of the American Constitution; Art. 95 of -the Constitution
of France,; Art.
95 of the Constitution of Finland; Art. 97 of
the Constitution of Cambodia; Art. 183 of the Constitution of Greece; Art. 97
of the Japanese Constitution; Art. 139 of the Italian Constitution, to mention
only a few.
When this happens the ordinary procedure of
amendment ,ceases to apply. The unlimited competence (the kompetenzkompetenz of
the Germans) does not flow from the amendatory process. Amendment can then be
by a fresh constituent body.
To attempt to do this otherwise is to attempt
a revolution.
I do not known why the word
"revolution", which I have used before, should evoke in some persons
an image of violence and subversion. The whole American Constitution was the
result of a bloodless revolution and in a sense so was ours.
The adoption of the whole Constitution and
the adoption of an amendment to the Constitution have much in common. An
amendment of the Constitution has been aptly called a Constitution in little
and the same question arises whether it is by a legal process or by revolution.
There is no third alternative. An amendment, which repeals the earlier
Constitution, unless legal, is achieved by revolution. As stated in the
American Jurisprudence :
"An attempt by the majority to change
the fundamental law in violation of self-imposed restrictions is
unconstitutional and revolutionary".(') There are illegal and violent
revolutions and illegal and peaceful revolutions. Modification of Constitution
can only be by the operation of a certain number of wills acting on other
wills. The pressure runs through a broad spectrum, harsh at one end and gentle
at the other. But whatever the pressure may be, kind or cruel, the revolution
is always there if the change is not legal. The difference is one of method,
not of kind. Political thinking starts from the few at the top and works
downward more often than in the reverse direction. It is wrong to think that
masses alone, called "the people" after Mazini, or "the
proletariate" after Marx, 'begin a revolutionary change. Political changes
are always preceded by changes in thought in a few. They may be outside the (1)
In the Constitution of Honduras, partial amendment only is possible. For a
complete amendment a Constituent Assembly has to be convoked. In the
Constitution of Brazil, the Constitution cannot be amended when there is a
state of seige (our emergency). In Turkey an amendment of Article 1 cannot even
be proposed.
(2) Vol. 12, Section 25 pp. 629-630.
865 Government or in it. It is a revolution
nevertheless, if an attempt is made to alter the will of the people in an
illegal manner. A revolution is successful only if there is consent and
acquiescence and a failure if there is not.
Courts can interfere to nullify the
revolutionary change because in all cases of revolution there is infraction of
existing legality. It is wrong to classify as revolution some thing coming from
outside the Government and an illegality committed by the Government against
the Constitution as evolution. I am mindful of the observations of Justice
Holmes, that"We need education in the obvious to learn to transcend our
own convictions and to leave room for much that we hold dear to be done away
with short of revolution, by the orderly change of law."(1) But the
problem we are faced with is not an orderly change of law but of a claim to a
revolutionary change against the vitals of the Constitution. In such a case the
apprehension is that democracy may be lost if there is no liberty based on law
and law based on equality. The protection of the fundamental Rights is
necessary so that we may not walk in fear of democracy itself.
Having assumed the distinction between
Government and' State let me now explain what I mean by that distinction and
what the force of Art. 13(2) in that context is. I shall begin first by reading
the pertinent article. Article 13 (2), which I quoted earlier, may again be
read here:
"13...............................
(2)The State shall not make any law which takes
away or abridges the rights conferred by this Part and any law made in
contravention of this clause shall, to the extent of contravention, be
void." The definition of the State in Art. 12 reads "12. In this
Part, unless the context otherwise requires, "the State" includes.the
Government and Parliament of India and the Government and the Legislature of
each of the States and all local or other authorities within the territory of
India or under the control of the Government of India." The State is the
sum total of all the agencies which are also individually mentioned in Art. 12
and by the definition all the parts severally are also included in the
prohibition. Now see how 'law' is defined:
"13.......................
(1) The Mind and Faith of Justice Holmes p.
390.
866 (3)In this article, unless the context
otherwise requires,(a) "law" includes any ordinance, order, bye-law,
rule, regulation, notification, custom or usage having in the territory of
India the force of law;" In Sajjan Singh's case(1) I said that if
amendments of the constitution were meant to be excluded from the word
"law" it was the easiest thing to add to the definition the further
words "but shall not include an amendment of the Constitution". it
'LS argued now before us that this wag not necessary because Art. 368 does not
make any exception.
This argument came at all stages like a
refrain and is the real cause of the obfuscation in the opposite view. Those
who entertain this thought do not pause to consider : why make a prohibition against
the State? As Cooley said:
"there never was a republican
Constitution which delegated to functionaries all the latent powers which lie
dormant in every nation and are boundless in extent. and incapable of
definition.", If the State wields more power than the functionaries there
must be a difference between the. State and its agencies such as Government,
Parliament, the Legislatures of the States and the local and other authorities.
Obviously, the State means more than any of there or all of them put together.
By making the State subject 'to Fundamental Rights it is clearly stated in Art.
13 (2) that any' ,of the agencies acting alone or all the agencies, acting
together are not above the Fundamental Rights. Therefore, when the House .of
the People or the Council of States introduces a Billfor the abridgement of the
Fundamental Rights, it ignores the injunction against it and even if the two
Houses pass the Bill the injunction is next operative against the President
since the expression "Government of India" in the General Clauses Act
means the President of India. This is equally true of ordinary laws and laws
seeking to amend the Constitution. The meaning of the word "State"
will become clear if I draw attention at this stage to Art. 325 of the Constitution
of Nicargua, which reads as follows:"325. The agencies of the Government,
jointly or separately, are, for-bidden to suspend the Constitution or to
restrict she rights granted by it, except in the cases provided therein."
In our Constitution the agencies of the State are controlled jointly and
separately and the prohibition is against the whole force of (1) [1965] 1
S.C.R. 933.
867 the State acting either in its executive
or legislative capacity. Ile of the Executive is more important than even the
Legislature. In modem politics run on parliamentary democracy the Cabinet
attains a position of dominance over the Legislature. The Executive, therefore,
can use the Legislature as a means of securing changes in the laws which it
desires. It happened in Germany under Hitler. The fact has been noticed by
numerous writers. for example, Wade and Philips(1), Sir Ivor Jennings(2) ,
Dawson(3), Keith(4) and Ramsay Muir(5). Dawson in particular said that a
Cabinet is no longer responsible to the Commons but the Commons has become
instead responsible to the Government. Ivor Jennings added that if a Government
had majority it could always secure the legislation. The others pointed out
that the position of the Cabinet towards Parliament tends to assume more or less
dictatorial powers and that was why people blamed Government, this is to say,
the Cabinet rather than Parliament for ineffective and harsh laws.
This is true of our country also regarding
administration and Station. Fortunately, this is avoided at least in so far as
the Fundamental Rights are concerned. Absolute, arbitrary power in defiance of
Fundamental Rights exist nowhere under our Constitution, not even in the
largest majority. The people's representatives have, of course, inalienable and
undisputable right to alter, reform or abolish the Government in any manner
they think fit, but the declarations of the Fundamental Rights of the citizens
are the inalienable rights of the people. Ile extent of the power of the rulers
at any time is, measured by the Fundamental Rights. It is wrong to think of
them as rights within the Parliament's giving or taking. Our Constitution
enables an individual to oppose successfully the whole community and the State
and claim his rights. This is because the Fundamental Rights are I so
safe-guarded that within the limits set by the Constitution they are inviolate.
The Constitution has itself said what protection has been created round the
person and property of the citizens and to what extent this protection may give
way to the general good. it is wrong to invoke the Directive Principles as if
there is some antinomy between them and the Fundamental Rights. The Directive
Principles lay down the routes of State but such action must avoid the
restrictions stated in the Fundamental Rights. Prof. Anderson (6) taking the
constitutional amendments, as they have been in our country, considered the
Directive principles to be more potent than the Fundamental (1) Constitutional
Law, 6th Edn. p. 27.
(2) Parliament (1957) pp. 11-12.
(3) Government of Canada (1952) Chapter XIX.
(4) An Introduction to British Constitutional
Law (1931) P.
48, (5) How Britain is Governed P. 5,6.
(6) Changing Law in Developing Countries, pp.
88, 89.
868 Rights. That they are not, is clear when
one takes the FundamentalRights. withthe guaranteed remedies. The Directive
Principles are not justiciable but the Fundamental Rights are' made
justiciable. This gives a judicial control and check over State action even
within the four corners of the Directive Principles. It cannot be conceived
that in following the Directive Principles the Fundamental Rights (say for
example, the equality clause) can be ignored. If it is attempted, then . the
action is capable of being struck down. In the same way, if an amendment of the
Constitution is law for the reasons explained by me, such an amendment is also
open to challenge under Art. 32, if it offends against the Fundamental Rights
by abridging or taking them away. Of course, it is always open to better
Fundamental Rights. A law or amendment of the Constitution would offend the
Fundamental Rights only when it attempts to abridge or take them away.
The importance of Fundamental Rights in the
world of today cannot be-lost sight of. On December 10, 1948, the General.
Assembly of the United Nations adopted the
Universal Declaration of Human Rights without a dissent. This draft was made
after the Third Committee of the United Nations had devoted 85 meetings to it.
The Declaration represents the civil, political and religious liberties for
which men have struggled through the centuries and those new social and
economic rights of the Individual which the Nations are increasingly
recognising in their Constitutions. Some of these were proclaimed during the
French Revolution and areincluded in the declarations of Nations taking pride
in the dignity and liberty of the Individual. They are epitomized in the
Preamble, and more fully expressed in Parts III and IV of our Constitution.
These Declarations wherever found are intended to give a key to social progress
by envisaging rights to work, to education and to'social insurance.
The Nations of the world are now in the
second stage, where Covenants are being signed on the-part of the States to
respect such rights. United Nations Human Rights Commission has worked to
produce two drafts-one dealing, with civil and political rights and the other
with economic, social and cultural rights., The third stage is still in its
infancy in which it is hoped to provide for the enforcement of these rights on
an international basis. The Regional Charter of the Human Rights under which
there is established already a European Commission of Human Rights to
investigate and report on violations of Human Rights, is a significant step in
that direction. After 1955 the European Commission has become competent to
receive complaints from individuals although the enforceability of Human Rights
on an international basis is still far from being achieved. If one compares the
Uni 869 versal Declaration with Parts III and IV of our Constitution one finds
remarkable similarity in the two. It is significant that our Committee on
Fundamental Rights was deliberating when the This Committee of the United
Nations was deliberating on the. Universal Declaration of Human Rights. Both
are manifestos of man's inviolable and fundamental freedoms.
While the world is anxious to secure
Fundamental Rights internationally, it is a little surprising that some
intellectuals in our country, whom we may call "classe non classe"
after Hegel, think of the Directive Principles in our Constitution as if they
were superior to Fundamental Rights. As a modern philosopher(1) said such
people 'do lip service' to freedom thinking all the time in terms of social
justice "with 'freedom' as a by-product". Therefore, in.
their scheme of things Fundamental Rights
become only an epitheton ornans. One does not know what they believe in the
communistic millennium of Marx or the individualistic Utopia of Bastiat. To
them an amendment of the Fundamental Rights is permissible if it can be said to
be within a scheme of a supposed socioeconomic reform, however, much the danger
to liberty, dignity and freedom of the Individual.
There are others who hold to liberty and
freedom of the.
Individual under all conditions. Compare the
attitude of Middleton Murray who would have Communism provided "there was
universal freedom of speech, of association, of elections and of
Parliament" To such the liberty and dignity of the Individual are
inviolable. Of course, the liberty of the individual under our Constitution,
though meant to be fundamental, is subject to such restrictions as the . needs
of society dictate. These are expressly mentioned in the Constitution itself in
the hope that no further limitations would require to be imposed at any time.
I do not for a moment suggest that the
question about reasonableness, expediency or desirability of the amendments of
the Constitution from a political angle is to be considered by the courts. But
what I do say is that the possession of the necessary majority does not put
'any party above the constitutional limitations implicit in the Constitution.
It is obvious that the Constituent Assembly in making the Fundamental Rights
justiciable was not justisfied with reliance on the sense of self-restraint or
public opinion(2) on which the majority in Sajjan Singh's(3) case does. This is
not argument of fear: The question to ask is : can a party, which enjoys 2/3rds
majority today, before it (1)Benedetto Croce.
(2)Sir Robert Peel calls it "that great
compound of foiiy, weakness, prejudice, wrong feeling, right feeling, obstinacy
and newspaper paragraphs" (3)[1965] 1 S.C.R. 933.
CI/67-10 870 loses it, amend Art. 368 in such
wise that a simple majority would be sufficient for the future amendments of
the constitution ? Suppose it did so, would there be any difference between the
constitutional and the Ordinary laws made thereafter ? The liberty of the
Individual has to be fundamental and it has been so declared by the people.
Parliament today is not the constituent body as the Constituent Assembly was,
but is a constituted body which must bear true, allegiance to the Constitution
'as by law established. To change the Fundamental part of the Individual's
liberty is a usurpation of constituent functions be-cause they have been placed
outside the scope of thepower of constituted. Parliament.
It is obvious that Parliament need not now
legislate at all.
It has spread the umbrella of Art. 31-B and
.has only to add, a clause that all legislation involving Fundamental Rights
would be deemed to be within that protection hereafter. Thus the only palladium
against legislative dictatorship may be removed by a 2/3rds majority not only
in praesanti but, defuturo. This can hardly be open to a constituted Parliament.
Having established, that there is no
difference between the ordinary legislative and the amending processes in so
far as cl.(2) of Aft. 13 is concerned, because both being laws in their true
character, come within the prohibition created, by that, clause against the
State and that the Directive Principles cannot be invoked to destroy
Fundamental Rights.
I proceed now to examine whether the English
and Amercan precedents lay down any principle applicable to amendments of our
Constitution. In, Britain the question whether a constitutional amendment is
valid or not at arise because the courts are powerless' Parliamentary
Sovereignty under the English Constitution means that Parliament enjoys the
right to make or unmake any law whatever and no person or body has any right to
question the legislation. The utmost and absolute despotic power belongs to
Parliament. It "make, confirm, enlarge, restrain, abrogate, repeal, revise
and expand law concerning matters of all possible denominations". What Parliament
does, no authority on earth can undo. The The Queen, each House of Parliament
the constituencies and the law courts have in the past claimed independent
legislative powers but these claims are unfounded. It is impossible to compare
the Indian Parliament with the Brittsh Parliament as the former concodedly in
the ordinary legislation is subject to judicial review, both on the ground of
competence arising from a federal structure And the existence of Fundamental
Rights.
The question of competence in the matter of
amendment of the Constitution depends upon, firstly, compliance with the
procedure laid down in Art. 368 and, secondly, upon the question
whether,the.process is in 871 any manner restricted by the Fundamental -Rights.
Such questions cannot obviously arise in the British Parliament(').
The example of the Constitution of the United
States cannot also serve any purpose although the greatest amount of support
was sought to be derived from the decisions of the Supreme Court and the
institutional writings in the United States. The power of amend in the United
States Constitution flows from Art. V. (1). It must be noticed that the power
is clearly not made equal to ordinary legislative process. One salient point of
difference is that the President is nowhere in' this scheme because his
negative does not run.(') The amendment is thus not of the same quality as
ordinary legislation.
The Supreme Court of the United States has no
doubt brushed aside objections to amendments of the Constitution on the score
of incompetence, but has refrained from giving any reasons. In the most
important of them, which questioned the 18th Amendment, the Court only stated
its conclusions.
After recalling the texts of the Article
under which Amendments may be made and of the 18th Amendment proposed by the
Congress in 1917 and proclaimed as ratified by the States in 1919, the Court
announced :
"4. The prohibition of the manufacture,
sale, transportation, importation, and exportation of intoxicating liquors for
beverage purposes, as embodied in the 18th amendment, Is within the power to
amend reserved by Art. 5 of the Constitution." (emphasis supplied) (4) One
would have very much liked to know why this proposition was laid down in the
terms emphasised above if the effective exercise of the. power depended upon a
particular procedure which was immaculately followed. The silence of the Court
about its reasons has been noticed in the same judgment by Mr. Justice (1)
Dicey gives three supposed limitations on the power of Parliament. Of these one
that language has been used in Acts of Parliament which implies that one
Parliament can make laws which cannot be touched by any subsequent Parliament,
is not true. The best examples are Act of treaties with Scotland and Ireland
but these same Acts have been amended later. Francis Bacon found this claim to
be -untenable. See Dicey 'The Law of the Constitution pp. 64, 65.
(2) Article V. The Congress, whenever
two-thirds of both houses shall deem it necessary, shall propose -amendments to
this Constitution, or, on the application of the legislatures of two-thirds of
the several States, shall call a convention for proposing amendments, which, in
either case, shall be valid to all intents and purposes, as part of this
Constitution, when ratified by the legislatures of three-fourths of the several
States, or by conventions in three-fourths thereof, as the one or the other
mode of ratification may be proposed by the Congress, provided that no
amendment which may be made prior to the year' one thousand eight hundred and
eight shall in any manner affect the first and fourth clauses in the ninth
section of the first article; and that no State, without its consent, shall be
deprived of its equal suffrage in the Senate." (3) Hollingsworth v.
Virginia 3 Dall. 378.
(4) National Prohibition Cases, 253 U.S. 350.
872 Mckenna. In feser v. Garnett(1) the Court
was hardly more expressive. The only question considered by the Court was
"The first contention is that the power of amendment conferred by the'
Federal Constitution, and sought to be exercised, does not dxtend to this
Amendment, because of its character." (emphasis supplied).
This was repelled by Brandeis, J on behalf of
the unanimous court on the grx)und that theAmendment was in character and
phraseology similar to the 15th Amendment and was adopted by following the same
method. As the,lsth Amendment had been accepted for half a century the
suggestion that it was not in accordance with law, but as a war measure
validated by acquiescence was not accepted.
It is significant, however, that at the time
of the 18th Amendment, the arguments were (a) that 'amendment' was' limited to
the correction of error in the framing of the Constitution, (b) Article V did
not comprehend the adoption of additional or supplementary provisions, (c)
ordinary legislation could not be embodied. in the constitutional amendment,
and (d) Congress could not 'propose amendment which pared the sovereign power
of the States. None of these at I guin ents was accepted. At the time of the 19th
Amendment, which increased the franchise in the States, the narrow ground was
that a State which had not ratified the Amendment would be, deprived of its
equal suffrage in the Senate because its representatives in that body would be
persons not of its choosing, i.e. persons,chosen by voters whom the State
itself had not authorised to vote for Senators. This argument was rejected.
However, in Dillion v. Gloss(2) the Supreme Court held that Congress had the,
power to a time limit for ratification because Art. V implied that application
must be within some reasonable time after. the proposal". The fixation of
7 years was held by the Court to be reasonable.
In 1939 came the case of Coleman v. Miller(3)
which dealt with the Child Labour Amendment. Such a law was earlier rejected by
the Kansas Leizislature. Later the State ratified the amendment after a lapse
of 13 years by the casting vote of the Lt. Governor. Mandamus was asked against
the Secretary of Kansas Senate to erase the endorsement of ratification from
its record and it was denied. The Supreme Court of Kansas refused to review
this denial on certiorari.
The Supreme Court of the United States in an
opinion, in which not more than 4 Justices (1) 258-U.S. 130. (2)256 U.S. 368.
(3) 307 U.S. 443.
873 took any particular view,. declined to
interfere. Majority affirmed the decision of Supreme Court of Kansas. Four
Justices considered that the question was political from start to finish and
three Justices that the previous rejection of the law and the extraordinary
time taken to ratify were political questions.
Although the Supreme Court has scrupulously
refrained from passing on the ambit of Art. V it has nowhere said that it will
not take jurisdiction in any case involving the amending process. (1) In Hollingsworth
v. Virginia(2) the supreme Court assumed that the question was legal. The
Attorney General did not even raise an objection. In Luther v. Borden($) the
matter was finally held to be political which opinion prevailed unimpaired
'till some doubts have arisen after Baker v. Carr(4). In the case the Court
remarked"We conclude...... that the non-justiciability of claims resting
on the guarantee clause which arises from the embodiment of questions that were
thought 'Political' can have no bearing upon the justiciability of the, equal
protection claim presented in this case......
We ernphasise that it is the involvement in
guarantee clause claims of the elements thought to define "political
questions" and no other feature, which could render them nonjusticiable.
specifically, We have said that such claims are not held non-justiciable
because they touch matters of State governmental Organisation.
It would appear that the Equal Protection
Clause was held to supply a guide for examination of apportionment methods
better than the Guarantee Clause.
Although there is no clear pronouncement, a
great controversy exists whether questions of substance can ever come before
the Court and whether there are any implied limitations upon the amendatory
Power. In the cases above noted, the other articles (particularly the Bill of
Rights) were not read as limitations and no limitation outside the amending
clause was implied. In the two cases inwhich the express limitation of Equal
suffrage Clause was involved the Court did not enter the question. Thus the
15th and, on its strength, the 19th Amendments were upheld. In Coleman v.
Miller(5) the political question doctrine
brought the support of only four Justices and in Baker v. Carr(4) the Federal,
Courts were held to have jurisdiction to scrutinise the fairness of legislative
apportionment, under the 14th Amendment and to take steps to assure that
serious inequities were wiped out.. The (1) See Rottschaeffer: Handbook of
American Constitutional Law (1939) pp. 397, 398, though the author's opinion is
that it will deny jurisdiction.
(2) 3 Dall. 378.
(3) 12 L. Ed. 58.
(4) 369 U.S. 186.
(5) 307 U. S. 443 874 courts have thus
entered the political thicket'.The question of delimitation of constituencies
cannot, of, course, arise before courts under our Constitution because of Art.
329.
Baker v. Carr(1) makes the Court sit in
judgement over the possession and distribution of politcal power which is an
essential part of a Constitution. The magical formula of "political questions"
is losing ground and it is to be hoped that a change may be Soon. coming. Many
of the attacks on the amendments were the result of a misunderstanding that the
Constitution Was a compact between States and that the allocation of powers was
not to be changed at all. This was finally decided by Texas v. White (2) as far
back as 1869.
The main question of implied limitations has
evoked a spate of writings. Bryce(s), Weaver(4), Mathews(5), Burdick(6),
Willoughby(7), Willis(8), Rottshaefer(9), Orfield(10) (to name only a few) are
of the opinion that there are no, implied limitations, although, as Cooley
points out, "it is sometimes expressly declared-what indeed is implied
without the declaration that everything in the declaration of rights contained
is excepted out of the general powers of Government, and all laws contrary
thereto shall be void(11)." Ex-press checks there are only three. Two
temporary checks were operative till 1808 and dealt with interference with
importation of slaves and the levying of a direct tax without apportionment
among then States according to population. Permanent check that now remains is
equality of representation of States in the Senate. Some writers suggest that
this, check may also be-removed in two moves.
By thefirst the Article can be, amended and
by the second the equality removed. When this happens it will be seen whether
the Supreme Court invokes any doctrine such as achieving. indirectly what
cannot be done directly.
It will, of course, be completely out of
place in a judgment to discuss the. views of the several writers and so I shall
confine myself to the observation of Orfield to whom again and again counsel
for the State turned either for support or inspiration. Accord. ing to him,
there are' no implied limitations unless the Courts adopt (1) 369 U.S. 186.
(2) Wall.700.
(3) The American Commonwealth Vol. I.
(4) Constitutional law and its Administration
(1946).
(5) American Constitutional System (2nd Edn.)
p. 43-45.
(6)The Law of the American Constitution (7th
Imp.) p. 45.
(7) Tagore Law Lectures (1924).
(8)constitutionaI Law of United States
(1936).
(9) Handbook of American Constitutional Law.
(10)The Amending of the Federal Constitution
(11)Constitutional Limitations Vol. I, 8th Edn. pp. 95, 96.
875 that view and therefore no limitations on
the substance of the amendments except the Equality Clause. His view is that
when Congress is in the amending process, it is not legislating but exercising
a peculiar power bestowed by Art.
V. I have already shown that under our
Constitution the amending process is a legislative process, the only difference
being a special majority and the existence of Art. 13(2). Orfield brushes aside
the argument that this would destroy the very concept of the Union which, as
Chief Justice. Marshall had said, was indestructible. Orfield faces boldly the
question whether the whole Constitution can be overthrown by an amendment and
answers yes. But he says that the amendment must not be in violation of the
Equality Clause. This seems to be a great concession. He makes this exception
but Munro(-'), who finds it difficult to conceive of an unamendable
constitution suggests that it should be possible to begin with that clause and
then the door to amendments would be wide open. Of course, the Supreme, Court
has not yet faced an amendment of this. character and it has not yet denied
jurisdiction to itself. In the.
United States the Constitution works because,
as observed by Willis, the Supreme Court is allowed to do "'the work of
remolding the Constitution to keep it abreast with new conditions and new
times, and to allow the agencies expressly endowed with the; amending process
to act only in extraordinary emergencies or when, the general opinion disagrees
with the opinion of the Supreme Court." In our country amendments, so far
have bean made only with the object of negativing the Supreme Court,decisions,
but more of it later.
I have referred to Orfield although there are
greater names than his expounding the same views. I have refrained from
referring to the opposite view which in the words of Willoughby has been
"strenuously argued by reputable writers" although Willis
discourteously referred to them in his book. My reason for not doing so is
plainly this. The process of amendment in the United States is clearly not a
legislative process and there is no provision like Art. 13 (2) under which
"laws" abridging or taking away Fundamental Rights can be declared
void. Our liberal Constitution has given to the Individual all that he should
have-freedom of speech, of association, of assembly, of religion, of motion and
locomotion, of property and trade and profession. In addition it has made the
State incapable of abridging or taking away these rights to the extent
guaranteed, and has itself shown how far the enjoyment of those rights can be
curtailed. It; has given a guaranteed right 'to the person affected to move the
Court.-, I-le guarantee is worthless if the rights are capable of being taken
away. This makes our Constitution unique and the American precedents cannot be
of much assistance.
(1) The Govenment of the United States (5th
Edn.) p. 77.
876 The Advocate General of Madras relied
upon Vedel.(1) According to Vedel, a prohibition in the Constitution against
its own amendment has a political but not juridical value, and from the
juridical point of view, a declaration of absolute constitutional immutability
cannot be imagined.
The constituent power being supreme, the
State cannot be fettered even by itself. He notices, however, that the Constitution
of 1791 limited the power of amendment (revision) for a certain time and that
of 1875 prohibited the alteration of the Republican form of Govermment. He
thinks that this hindrance can be removed by a two step amendment. He concludes
that the constituent of today cannot bind the nation of tomorrow and no
Constitution can prohibit its amendOf course, the French have experimented with
over a dozen Constitutions, all very much alike, while the British have slowly
changed their entire structure from a monarchical executive to an executive
from Parliament and have reduced the power of the House of Lords.
Cambell-Bannerman former Prime Minister of England summed up the difference to
Ambassador M. de Fleurian thus :
".... Quand nous faisons une Revolution,
nous ne ditruisons pas notre maison, nous en conservons avec soin la facade,
et, derriere cette facade, nous reconstruisons une nouvelle maison. Vous,
Francais, agissez autrement; vous jetez bas le vieil edifice et vous
reconstruisez la mime maison avec une autre facade et sous un nom
different." (When we make a Revolution we do not destroy an house, we save
with care the facade and behind construct a new house. You, Frenchmen, act
differently. You throw down the old edifice and you reconstruct the same house
with a different facade and under a different name).
M.de Fleurian agreed that there was a lot of
truth in it (ll ya du vrai dans cette boutade) (2).
But of course to a Frenchman brought up in a
legal system in which the Courts do not declare even an ordinary statute to be
invalid, the idea of the unconstitutionality of a constitutional amendment does
not even occur. France and Belgium have created no machinery for questioning
legislation and rely on moral and political sanctions. Even an English lawyer
and less so an American lawyer find it difficult to understand how the legality
of an amendment of the Constitution can ever be questioned. It (1) Mannual
Elementaire da Droil Constitutional (Sirey) p..
117.
(2) Recounted by M. de Fleuriau in the Preface
to J. Magnan de Bornier, L'Empire Britannique, son evolution politique et
constitutionnelle p. 6, quoted in Wheare: The Statute of Westminster and
Dominion status, P. 9-10.
877 appears to them that the procedure for
the amendment being gone through there is no one to question and what emerges
is the Constitution as valid as the old Constitution and just as binding. The
matter, however, has to be looked at in this way. Where the Constitution is
overthrown and the Courts lose their position under the old Constitution, they
may not be able to pass on the validity of the new Constitution. This is the,
result of a revolution pure and simple. Where the new Constitution is not
accepted and the people have not acquiesced in the change and the courts under
the old Constitution function, the courts can declare the new Constitution to
be void. Perhaps even when the people acquiesce and a new Government comes into
being, the courts may still declare the new Constitution to be invalid but only
if moved to do so. It is only when the courts begin to function under the new
Constitution that they cannot consider the vires of that Constitution because
then they owe their existence to it. I agree with Or field in these
observations taken from his book. He, however, does not include amendments of
the Constitution in these remarks and expressly omits them. His opinion seems
to indicate that in the case of amendments courts are completely free to see
that the prescribed constitutional mode, of alteration is complied with and the
alteration is within the permissive limits to which the Constitution wishes the
amendments to go. This is true of all amendments but particularly of an
amendment seeking to repeal the courts' decision and being small in dimension,
leaves the courts free to consider its validity. The courts derive the power
from the existing terms of the Constitution and the amendment fails if it seeks
to overbear some existing restriction on legislation.
What I have said does not mean that
Fundamental Rights are not subject to change or modification. In the most
inalienable of such rights a distinction must be made between possession of a
right and its exercise. The first is fixed and the latter controlled by justice
and necessity.
Take for example Art. 21 :
"No person shall be deprived of his life
or personal liberty except according to procedure established by law".
Of all the rights, the right to one's life,
is the most valuable. This article of the Constitution, therefore, makes. the
right fundamental. But the inalienable right is curtailed by a murderer's
conduct as viewed under law. The deprivation, when it takes place, is not of
the right which was immutable but of the continued exercise of the right.
Take a Directive Principle which is not
enforceable at law but where the same result is reached. The right to employment
is a directive principle. Some countries even view it as a Fundamental Right.
The exercise, however, of that right must depend upon the capacity of Society
to afford employment to all 878 and sundry. The possession of this right cannot
be confused with its exercise. One right here is positive and can be enforced
although its, exercise can be curtailed or taken away, the other is a right
which, the State must try to give but which cannot be enforced. The
Constitution permits a curtailment of the exercise of most of the Fundamental
Rights by stating the limits of that curtailment. But this power does not
permit the, State itself, to take away or abridge the right beyond the limits
set by the Constitution.
It must also be remembered that the rights of
one% individual are often opposed by the rights of another individual and thus
also become limitative. The Constitution in this way" permits the
Fundamental Rights to be controlled in their exercise but prohibits their
erasure.
It is argued that such approach makes Society
static and robs the State of its sovereignty. It is submitted that it leaves
revolution as the holy alternative if change is necessary. This is not right.
The whole Constitution is open to amendment only two dozen articles are outside
the reach of Art. 368. That too because the Constitution has made them
fundamental. What is being suggested by the counsel or the State is itself a
revolution, because as things are that method of,amendment is illegal. There is
a legal method. Parliament must act in a different way reach the Fundamental
Rights. The State must reproduce the power which it has chosen to put under a
restraint. Just as the French or the Japanese,etc. cannot change the articles
of their Constitution which are, made free, from the power of amendment and'
must call a convention or a constituent body, so also we' India cannot abridge
or take away the Fundamental Rights by the ordinary amending process.
Parliament must amend Art. 369 to convoke
another Constituent Assembly pass a law under item 97 of the First List of
Schedule VII to call a Constituent Assembly and then that assembly may be able
to abridge or take away the Fundamental Rights if desired. It cannot be done
otherwise.
The majority in Sajjan Singh's case(1)
suggested bringing Art. 32 under the Proviso to improve protection to the
Fundamental Rights. Article 32 does not stand in need of this Protection. To
abridge or take away that article (and the same is true of all other
Fundamental Rights) a constituent body and not a constituted body is required.
Parliament today is a constituted body with
powers of legislation which include amendments of the Constitution by a special
majority but only so far as Art. 13 (2) allows.
To bring into existence a constituent body is
not impossible as, I had ventured to suggest during the hearing and which I
have now more fully explained here.It may be said that. this is not necessary
because Art. 368 can be amended by Parliament to confer on itself constituent
powers over the Fundamental Rights. This would he wrong and againstArt.
13 (2). Parliament cannot. increase its (1)
[1965] 1 S.C.R. 933.
879 powers in this way and do indirectly
which it is intended not to de. directly. The State does not lose its
sovereignty. but as it has chosen. to create, self-imposed restrictions through
one constituent body those restrictions cannot be ignored by a constituted body
which makes laws.
Laws so made can affect those parts of the
Constitution which are outside the restriction in Art. 13 (2) but any'law
(legislative or mendatory) passed by such a body must conform to that article.
To be able to abridge, or take away the Fundamental Rights which give so many
assurances and guarantees a fresh Constituent Assembly must be, convoked.
Without such action the protection of the Fundamental Rights must remain
immutable and any attempt to abridge or take them away in any other way must be
regarded as revolutionary.
I shall now consider the amendments of the
Fundamental Rights made since the adoption of the Constitution, with a view to
illustrating my meaning. Part III is divided under different headings. They are
(a), General (b) Right to Eqility (c) Right to Freedom (d) Right against
exploitation (e) Right to Freedom of Religion (f) Cultural and Educational
Rights (g) Right to Property (h) Right to Constitutional Remedies. I shall
first deal with amendments of topics other than the topic (g)Right to Property.
'The articles which are amended in the past are Art 15 & and 19 by the 1st
Amendment (18th June 1951) and Art, 16 by the 7th Amendment (19th October
1956). The 16th Amendment added the words "the sovereignty and integrity
of India to some clauses. As that does not abridge or take away any Fundamental
Right, I shall not refer to the 16th Amendment hereafter. That Amendment was
valid. The changes so made may be summarized. In Art. 15, which deals with.
prohibition or discrimination on the ground
of religion, race, caste, sex or place of birth, clause (3) allowed the State
to make special provision for women and children. A new clause was added which
reads:
"(4) Nothing in this article or in
clause (2) of article 29 shall prevent the State from making any special
provision for the advancement of any socially and educationally backward
classes of citizens or for the Scheduled Castes and the Scheduled Tribes".
It is argued by counsel for the State that by
lifting the ban to make specialprovision for backward classes of citizens,
there is discrimination against the higher classes. This is the view which
classes in a privileged position who had discriminated against the backward
,classes for centuries, might indeed take. But I cannot accept this contention.
The Constitution is intended to secure to all citizens "Justice, social,
economic and political and Equality of status and opportunity" (vide the
Preamble) and the Directive Principles include Art. 38 which provides:
880 .lm15 "38 The State shall strive to
promote the welfare of the people by securing and protecting as effectively as
it may a social order in which justice, social, economic and political, shall
inform all the institutions of the national life." To remove the effect of
centuries of discriminatory treatment and to raise the down-trodden to an equal
status cannot be regarded ,as discriminatory against any one. It is no doubt
true that in State of Madras v.. Champakam(1) the reservation of seats for
Backward Classes, Scheduled Castes and Tribes in public educational
institutions was considered invalid. Articles 16(4) and 340 had already
provided for special treatment for these backward ,classes and Art. 46 had
provided that the State shall promote, with special care their educational and
economic interests. With all ,due respects the question of discrimination
hardly arose because in view of these provisions any reasonable attempt to
raise the status of the backward classes could have been upheld on the
principle of classification. In any event, the inclusion of this clause to Art.
16 does not abridge or take away any one's Fundamental Rights unless the view
be taken that the backward classes for ever must remain backward.
By the First Amendment the second and the
sixth clauses of Art. 19 were also amended. The original cl. (2) was
substituted by a new clause and certain words were added in clause (6). The
changes may be seen by comparing the unamended and the amended clauses side by
side :
"19( 1) All citizens shall have the
right(a) to freedom of speech and expression;
(2) (Before Amendment) (After Amendment)
Nothing in sub-clause (a) of clause (1), Nothing in subclause (a) of clause
(1)shall affect the operation of any existing law in so far as it relates to,
or prevent the State from making any law relating to libel, slander,
defamation, contempt of Court or any matter which offends against decency or
morality or which undermines the security or tends to overthrow, the State.
shall affect the operation of any existing law, or prevent the State from
making any law. in so far as such law imposes reasonable restrictions on the
exercise of the right conferred by the said subclause in the interest of the...
security of the State, friendly relations with foreign States, public order,
decency or morality, or in relation to contempt of court, defamation or
incitement to an offence, The amendment was necessary because in Romesh Thapar
v State of Madras(2) it was held that disturbances of public tranquallity did
not come within the expression "undermines the secu(1)[1951]S.C.R.525.
(2) [1950] S.C.R. 594.
881 rity of the State". Later the
Supreme Court itself observed in the State of Bihar v. Shailabala Devi(1) that
this Court did not intend to lay down that an offence against public order
could not in any case come within that expression.
The changes related to (a) "friendly
relations with foreign States", (b) "public order" and (c)
"incitement to an offence" and the words ."undermines the
security of the State or tends to, overthrow the State". were replaced by
the words "in the interests of the security of the State".
This change could be made in view of the
existing provisions of the clause as the later decision of this Court above
cited 'clearly show that "public order" and "incitement to
offence" were already comprehended. The amendment was within the
permissible limits as it did not abridge or take away any Fundamental Right.
The Amending Act passed by Parliament also
included a subsection which read "(2) No law in force in the territory of
India, immediately before the commencement of the Constitution which is
consistent with the provisions of article 19 of the Constitution as amended by
sub-section (1) of this section shall be deemed to be void, or ever to have
become void, on the ground only that being a law which takes away or abridges
the right conferred by sub-clause (a) of clause ( I ) of the said article, its
operation was not saved by clause (2) of that article as originally enacted.
Explanation.-In this sub-section, the
expression "law in force" has the same meaning as in clause (1) of
article 1 3 of this Constitution".
This sub-section was not included in the
Constitution. That device was followed in respect of certain State statutes
dealing with property rights by including them in a now Schedule. It did not
then occur to Parliament that the laws could be placed. under a special
umbrella of constitutional protection. Perhaps it was not considered' necessary
because Art. 19(2) was retrospectively changed, and the, enactment of this
sub-section was an ordinary legislative action. If the amendment had failed,
the second subsection of section 3 would not have availed at all.
Tuming now to clause (6), we may read the
original and the amended clause side by side "19(1) All citizens shall
have the right= (g) to practise any profession, or to carry on any occupation,
trade or business.
(1) [1952] S.C.R. 654.
882 (6) (Before, Amendment) Nothing, in
sub-clause (g) of the said clause shall affect the operation of any existing
law in so far as it imposes, or prevent the State from making any law imposing,
in the interests of the general public, reasonable restrictions on the exercise
of the right conferred by the said sub-clause, and, in particular nothing in
the said sub-clause, shall affect the operation of any existing law in so far as
it prescribes or empowers any authority to prescribe, or prevent the State from
making any law prescribing or empowering any authority to prescribe, the
professional or technical qualifications necessary for practising any
profession or carrying on any occupation, trade or business.
(After Amendment) Nothing in sub-clause (g)
of the said clause shall affect the operation of any existing law in so far as
it imposes, or prevent the State from making any law imposing, in the interests
of the general public, reasonable restrictions on the exercise of the right
conferred by the said sub-clause, and, in particular, nothing in the said
sub-clause, shall affect the operation of any existing law in so far as it
relates to, or prevent the State from making any law relating to,(i)the
professional or technical qualifications necessary for practising any
profession or carrying on any occupation, trade or business, or (ii)the
carrying on by the State, or a corporation owned or controlled by the State, of
any trade, business, industry or service, whether to the exclusion, complete or
partial, of citizens or otherwise, The first change is in the verbiage and is
not one of substance. It -only removes some unnecessary words. The new
sub-clause is innocuous except where it provides for the exclusion of citizens.
It enables nationalisation of industries and trade. Sub-clause (g) (to the
generality of which the original clause (6) created some exceptions) allowed
the State to make laws imposing, in the interests of the general public,
reasonable restrictions on the exercise of the right conferred by the
sub-clause. A law creating restrictions can, of course, be made outside the
Constitution or inside it. If it was considered that this right in the state
was required in the interests of the general public, then the exercise of the
right to practise profession or to carry on an occupation, trade or business
could be suitably curtailed. It cannot be said that nationalisation is never in
the interest of the general public. This amendment was thus within the
provision for restricting the exercise of the Fundamental Right in sub-cl.
(g) and was perfectly in order.
The Seventh Amendment introduced certain
words in Art. 16 (3). 'no clauses may be, compared:
" 16.
(3) (Before Amendment) Nothing in this
article shall prevent Parliament from making any law prescribing, in regard to
a class or classes of employment or appointment to an office under any State
specified in the First Schedule or any local or other authority within its
territory, any requirement as to residence within the 'State prior to such
employment or appointment.
(After Amendment) Nothing in this article
shall prevent Parliament from making any law prescribing, in regard to a class
or classes of employment or appointment to an office under the Government of,
or any local authority within, a State or Union territory, any requirement as
to residence within that State or Union territory prior to such employment or
appointment." 883 The change, is necessary to include a reference to Union
territory. It has no breaking upon Fundamental Rights., and, neither abridges
nor, takes away any of them. In the result none of the, amendments, of the
article. in parts other than that dealing with Right to property is, outside
the amending process because Art. 13(2) is in no manner breached.
This brings me, to the main question in this
case,, It is whether the amendments of the part Right to Property in Part, III
of the Constitution were legally made or not. To understand this part of the case
I must first begin by discussing what property rights mean and how they were
safeguarded by the Constitution as it was originally framed.
"Right to Property"in Part III was
originally the subject of one article, namely, Art. 31. Today there are three articles
3 1, 3 1 A and 31-B and the Ninth Schedule. The original thirty-first article
read:
"31 Compulsory acquisition of property.
(1) Nov person shall be deprived of his
property save by authority of law.
(2) 'No property, movable or immovable, including
any interest in or in any company owning, any commercial or industrial
undertaking, shall be taken possession of or acquired for public purposes under
any law authorising the taking of such possession or such acquisition, unless
the law provides for compensation for the property taken possession of or
acquired and either fixes the amount of the compensation, or specifies the
principle on which, and the manner. in which, the compensation is, to be
determined and given.
No such law as is referred to in clause. (2)
made by the Legislature of the State shall have effect unless such law, having
been reserved for the consideration of the President, has received his assent.
(4) If any Bill pending at the commencement
of this Constitution in the Legislature of a State has, 'after it has been
passed by such Legislature, been reserved for the consideration of the
President and has received his assent, then, notwithstanding anything in this
constitution, the law so assented to shall not be Called in question in any,
court on the ground that it contravenes the provisions of clause (2).
(5) Nothing in clause(2) shall affect(a) the
provisions of any existing law other than a law to which the provisions of
clause (6) apply,.or 884 (b) the provisions of any law which the State may
hereafter make(i) for the ,purpose of imposing or levying any tax or penalty,
or (ii) for the promotion of public health or the prevention of danger to life
or property, or (iii) in pursuance of any agreement entered into between the
Government of the Dominion of India or the Government of India and the
Government of . any other country, or otherwise, with respect to property
declared by law to be evacuee property.
(6) Any law of the State enacted not more
than eighteen months before the commencement of this Constitution may within
three months from such commencement be submitted to the President for his
certification; and thereupon, if the President by public notification so
certifies, it shall not be called in question in any court on the ground that
it contravenes the provisions of clause (2) of this article or has contravened
the provisions of sub-section (2) of section 299 of the Government of India,
Act, 1935".
The provisions of this article are intended
to be read with Art. 19(1) (f) which reads "19(1) All citizens shall have
the right(f) to acquire, hold and dispose of property".
Article 19 1 ) (f ) 'is subject to clause (6)
which I have already set out elsewhere and considered. Ownership and exchange
of property are thus recognised by the article.
The word "property" is is not
defined and I shall presently consider what may be included in 'property'.
Whatever the nature of property, it is clear that by the first clause of Art. 3
1 the right to property may be taken away under authority of law. This was
subject to one condition under the original Art. 3 1, namely, that the law must
either fix the compensation for the deprivation or specify the principles on
which and the manner in which compensation was to, be determined and given.
This was the heart of the institution 'of property as understood by the
Constituent Assembly. The rest of the article only gave constitutional support
against the second clause, to legislation already on foot in the States. This
created a Fundamental Right in property. The question may now be 885,
asked,:whywas it necessary to make such a Fundamental Right at all ? There is
no natural right in property and as Burke said in his Reflections, Government
is not made in virtue of natural rights, which may and do exist in total
independence of it.
Natural rights embrace activity outside the
status of citizen. Legal rights are required for free existence as a social
being and the State undertakes to protect them.
Fundamental Rights are those rights which the
State enforces against itself. Looking at the matter briefly but historically,
it may be said that the Greeks were not aware of these distinctions for as
Gierke(1) points out they did not distinguish between personality as a citizen
and personality as a human being. For them the Individual was merged in the
citizen and the citizen in the State. There was personal liberty and private
law but there was no sharp division between the different kinds of laws. The
Romans evolved this gradually not when the Roman Republic existed, but when the
notion of a Fiscus developed in the Empire And the legal personality of the
Individual was separated from his membership of the State. It was then that the
State began to recognize the rights of the Individual in his dealings with the
State. It was Cicero(2) who was the first to declare that the' primary duty of
the Governor of a State was to secure to each individual in the possession of
his property. Here we may see a recognition of the ownership of property as a
Fundamental Right. This idea wasso engrained in early social philosophy that we
find Locke opining in his Civil Government' (Ch. 7) that "Government has
no other end but the preservation of property". The concepts of liberty,
equality and religious freedom were well-known. To them was added the concept
of property rights. Later the list included "equalitas, libertas ius
securitatis, ius defensionis and ius puniendi. The concept of property right
gained further support from Bentham and Spencer and Kant and Hegel(3). The term
property in its pristine meaning embraced only land but it soon came to mean
much more.
According to Noyes(4)_ "Property is any
protected right or bundle of rights (interest or thing) with direct, or
indirect regard to any external object (i.e.
other than the person himself) which is
material or quasi material (i.e. a protected ,process) and which the then and
there Organisation of Society permits to be either private or public, which is
connoted by the legal concepts of occupying, possessing or, using".
(1) Das Doutscheg Genossenschaftrecht (III,
10).
(2) De Off. (The Offices) It Ch. XXI
(Everyman) p. 105.
(3) W. Friedman:Legal Theory (4th Edn.) see
pp. 373-376.
(4) The Institution of Property (1936) p.
436.
L3Sup CI/67-11 886 The right is enforced by
excluding entry or interference by a per. son not legally entitled. The
position of the State vis a vis the individual is the subject of Arts. 19 and
31, 31-A and 31-B.
Now in the enjoyment, the ultimate right may
be an interest which is connected to the object through a series of
intermediaries in which each 'holder' from the last to the first 'holds of'
'the holder' before him. Time was when there was a lot of 'free property' which
was open for appropriation. As Noyes(') puts it, "all physical manifestations
capable of being detected, localised and identified" can be the objects of
property. One exception now made by all civilized nations is that humanbeings
are no longer appropriable. If any free property was available then it could be
brought into possession and ownership by mere taking. It has been very aptly
said that all private property is a system of monopolies and the right to
monopolise lies at the foundation of the institution of property. Pound(-) in
classifying right in rem puts private property along with personal integrity
[right against injury to life, body and health (bodily or mental), personal
liberty (free motion and locomotion)], Society and control of one's family and
dependents. An extremely valuable definition of ownership is to be found in the
Restatement of the Law of Property where it is said :
"It is the totality of rights as to any
specific objects which are accorded by law, at any time and place, after
deducting social reservations".
This is the core from which some rights may
be detached but to which they must return when liberated.
The right to property in its primordial
meaning involved the acquisition, of 'a free object by -possession and
conversion of this possession into ownership by the protection of State or the
ability to exclude interference. As the notion of a State grew, the right of
property was strong or we according to the force of political opinion backing
it or the legislative support of the State. The English considered the right as
the, foundation of society. Blackstone(&) explained it on religious; and
social ground% claiming universality for it and called it the right of the
English people. William' Paley(4),although he thought the institution
paradoxical and unnatural found it full of advantage and Mackintosh in his
famous diatribe against the French Revolution described it as the
"sheet-anchorof society". This in"stitution' appeared in the
Magna Carta, in the American Declaration of Independence and the French
Declaration of Rights of Man. Later we find it in many (1) The Institution of
Property (1936)p. 438.
(2) Readings; p. 420.
3) Commentaries.
(4) Moral Philosophy.
887 Constitutions described as Fundamental,
general and guaranteed(1).
Our Constitution accepted the theory that
Right of Property is a fundamental right. In my opinion it was an error to
place it in that category. Like the original Art. 16 of the Draft Bill of the
Constitution which assured freedom of trade, commerce and intercourse within
the territory of India as a fundamental right but was later removed, the right
of property should have been placed in a different chapter. Of all the
fundamental rights it is the weakest.
Even in the most democratic of Constitutions,
(namely, the West German Constitution of 1949) there was a provision that
lands, minerals and means of production might be socialised or subjected to
control. Art. 31, if it contemplated socialization in the same way in India
should not have insisted so plainly upon payment of compensation. Several
speakers warned Pandit Nehru and others of the danger of the second clause of
Art. 31, but it seems that the Constituent Assembly was quite content that
under it the Judiciary would have no say in the matter of compensation. Perhaps
the dead hand of s. 299 of the Constitution Act of 1935 was upon the
Constituent Assembly. Ignored were the resolutions passed by the National
Planning Committee of the Congress (1941) which had advocated the co-operative
principle for exploitation of land, the Resolution of 1947 that land with its
mineral resources and all other means of production as well as distribution and
exchange must belong to and be regulated by the Community, and the warning of
Mahatma Gandhi that if compensation had to be paid we would have to rob Peter
to pay Paul(2) In the Constituent Assembly, the Congress (Which wielded the
majority then, as it does today) was satisfied with the Reprt of the Congress
Agrarian Reforms Committee 1949 which declared itself in favour of the
elimination of all intermediaries between the State and the tiller and
imposition of prohibition against subletting.
The Abolition Bills were the result.
Obviously the Sardar Patel Committee on Fundamental Rights was not prepared to
go far. In the debates that followed, many amendments and suggestions to alter
the draft article protecting property, failed. The attitude was summed up by
Sardar Patel. He conceded that land would be required for public purposes but
hopefully added : "not only land but so many other things may have to be
acquired. And the State will acquire them after paying compensation and not
expropriate thenm". (3) (1) Under the Constitution of Norway the rights
(Odels and Asaete rights) cannot be abolished but if the State requires the
owner must surrender the property and he is compensated.
(2) Gandhi : Constituent Assembly Debates
Vol. IX pp.
1204-06.
(3) Patel : Constituent Assembly Debates Vol.
I p. 517.
888 What was then the theory about Rightto
Property accepted by the Constituent Assembly ? Again I can only describe it
historically. Grotius(1) had treated the right as acquired right (ius
quaesitum) and ownership (dominium) as either serving individual interests
(vulgare) or for the public good (eminens). According to him, the acquired
right had to give way to eminent domain (ex vi auper-eminentis dominii) but
there must be public interest (publicautilitas) and if possible compensation.
In-the social contract theory also . the contract included protection of
property with recognition of the power of the ruler to act in the public
interest and emergency. Our constitutional theory treated property rights as
inviolable except through law for public good and on payment of compensation.
Our Constitution saw the matter in the way of Grotius but overlooked the
possibility that just compensation may. not be possible. It follows almost
literally the German jurist Ulrich Zasius (except in one respect) : Princeps
non potest auferee mihi rem mean sive iure gentium, sive civile sit facta mea.
All would, have been well if the Courts had construed
Article 31 differently. However, the decisions of the High Courts and the
Supreme Court, interpreting and expounding this philosophy took a different
view of compensation. I shall refer only to some of them., First the Patna High
Court in. Kameshwar v. Bihar(2) applied Art. 14 to strike down the Reforms Act
in Bihar holding it to be discriminatory. This need not have occasioned an
amendment because the matter could have been righted, as indeed it wag, by,an
appeal to the Supreme Court [see State of Bihar v. Kameshwar(3)].The
Constitution (First Amendment) Act, 1951 followed. It left Art. 31 intact but
added two fresh articles, Arts. 31-A and 31-B which are respectively headed
"saving of laws providing for acquisition of estates etc." and
"Validation of certain Acts and Regulations" and added a schedule
(Ninth) to be read with Art 31-B naming thirteen Acts of the State
Legislatures. Article 31-A was deemed always to have been inserted and Art.
31-B wiped out retrospectively all decisions of the courts which had.
declared any of the scheduled Acts to be
invalid. The texts of these new articles may now be seen:
"31A. Saving of laws providing for
acquisition of estates, etc.(1) Notwithstanding anything in foregoing
provisions of this Part, no law providing for the acquisition by the State of
any estate or of any rights therein or for (1) Grotius : De jure Belli ac
Pacis. 11 c. 2 2 (5)6. 1 c. I 6 and II c.
14 7 and 8.
(2) A.L.R. 1951 Patna 91.
(3) [1952] S.C.R. 889.
889 the extinguishment or modification of any
such rights shall be deemed to be void on the:
ground that it is consistent with, or takes
away or abridges any of the rights conferred by, any provisions of this Part
Provided that where such law is a law made by the Legislature of a State, the
provisions of this article shall not apply thereto unless such law, having been
reserved for the consideration of the President, has received his assent.
(2) In this article, (a) the expression
"estate" shall, in relation to any local area, have the same meaning
as that expression or its local equivalent has in the existing law relating to
land tenures in force in that area, and shall also include any jagir, inam or
muafi or other similar grant;
(b) the expression "right" in
relation to an estate shall include 'any rights vesting in a proprietor,
sub-proprietor, tenure-holder or other intermediary and any rights or
privileges in respect of land revenue." "31-B. Validation of certain
Acts and Regulations.
Without prejudice to the generality of the
provisions contained in article 31A, none of the Acts and Regulations specified
in the Ninth Schedule nor any of the provisions thereof shall be deemed to be
void, or ever to have become void, on the ground that such Act, Regulation or
provision is inconsistent with, or takes away or abridges any of the rights
conferred by, any provision of this Part, and notwithstanding any judgment,
decree or order of any court or tribunal to the, contrary, each of the said
Acts and Regulations shall, subject to-the power of any competent Legislature
to repeat or amend it, continue in force'." Article 31-A has been a
Protean article. It has changed its face many times. Article 31-B has remained
the same till today but the Ninth Schedule has grown.. The Constitution (Fourth
Amendment) Act, 1955, took the number of the Scheduled statutes to 20 and the
Constitution (Seventeenth Amendment) Act, 1964 to 64 and a so-called
explanation which saved the application of the Proviso in Art. 31-A, was also
added. The device [approved by Sankari Prasad's case(1)] was,found so (1)
[1952] 1 S.C.R. 89.
890 attractive that many more Acts were
sought to be included but were dropped on second thoughts. Even so, one wonders
how the Railway Companies (Emergency Provisions) Act, 1951,
The West Bengal Land Development and Planning Act and some others could have
been thought of in this connection. By this device, which can be extended
easily to other spheres, the Fundamental Rights can be completely emasculated
by a 2/3 majority, even though they cannot be touched in the ordinary way by a
unanimousvote of the same body of men! The State Legislatures may drive a coach
and pair through the Fundamental Rights and the Parliament by 2/3 majority will
then put them outside the jurisdiction of the courts.
Was it really intended that the restriction
against the State in Arts. 13(2) might be overcome by the two agencies acting
hand in hand ? Article 3 1 A dealt with the acquisition by the State of an
.estate' or of any rights therein or the extinguishment or modification of any
such rights. A law of the State could do these with the President's assent,
although,it took away or abridged any of the rights conferred by any provisions
of Part Ill. The words 'estate' and 'rights in relation to an estate' were
defined. The constitutional amendment was challenged in Sankari Prasad's
case(1) on various grounds but was upheld mainly on two grounds to which I
objected in Sajjan Singh's case(2). I have shown in this judgment, for reasons
which I need not repeat and which must be read in addition to what I said on
the earlier occasion, that I disagree respectfully but strongly with the view
of the Court in those two cases. This touches the first part of the amendment
which created Art.31-A. I do not and cannot question Art.31-A because (a) it
was not considered at the hearing of this case, and (b) it has stood for a long
time as part of the Constitution under the decision of this Court and has been
acquiesced in by the people. If I was free I should say that the amendment was
not legal and certainly not justified by the reasons given in the earlier cases
of this Court. Under the original Art.
31, compensation had to be paid for
acquisition by the State. This was the minimum requirement of Art. 31 (1) and
(2) and no amendment could be made by a constituted parliament to avoid
compensation. A law made by a constituted Parliament had to conform to Art.
13(2) and Art.
31 could not be ignored.
In 1954 the Supreme Court in a series of
cases drew the distinction between Art. 19(1)(f) and Art. 31, particularly in
West Bengal v. Subodh Gopal(3), Dwarkadas Srinivas v.
Sholapur Spinning Co. (4). In State of I West
Bengal v.
Mrs. Bela Banerjee and Others(5), this Court
held a compensation in Art. 31(2) meant (1) [1952] S.C.R. 89. (2) [1965] 1
S.C.R. 933.
(3)[1954] S.CR. 587. (4) [1954] S.CR. 558.
(5) [1954] S.C.R. 678.
891 just equivalent, i.e. full and fair money
equivalent' thus making the adequacy of compensation justiciable.
The Constitution (Fourth Amendment) Act, 1955
then amended both Art. 31 and Art. 31-A. Clause (2) of Art.. 31 was substituted
by"(2) No property shall be compulsorily acquired or requisitioned save
for a public purpose and save by authority of a law which provides for
compensation for the property so acquired or requisitioned and other fixes the
amount of the compensation or specifies the principles on which, and the manner
in which, the compensation is to be determined and given; and no such law shall
be called in question in any court on the ground that the compensation provided
by that law is not adequate".
The opening words of the former second clause
were modified to make them more effective but the muzzling of courts in the
matter of adequacy of the compensation was the important move. As Basu says :
"It is evident that the 1955 amendment
of clause (2) eats into the vitals of the constitutional mandate to pay
Compensation and demonstrate a drift from the meetings of the American concept
of private Property and judicial review to which our Constitution was hitherto
tied, to that of socialism."(1) It is appropriate to recall here that as
expounded by Professor Beard (2) (whose views offended Holmes and the Times of
New York but which are now being recognised after his further explanation(3)
the Constitution of the United States is an economic document prepared by men
who were wealthy or allied with property rights, that it is based on the
concept that the fundamental rights of property are anterior to Government and
morally beyond the, reach of popular majorities and that the Supreme Court of
the United States preserved the property rights till the New Deal era.
The, threat at that time was to enlarge the
Supreme Court but not to amend the Constitution. It appears that the Indian
Socialists charged with the idea of Marx, the Webbs, Green, Laski and others
viewed property rights in a different way. Pandit Nehru once said that he had
no property sense,meaning that he did not value property at all. The
Constitution seems to have changed its property significantly. In addition to
avoiding (1) Basu : commentaries on the Constitution of India (5th Edn.) Vol. 2
p. 230.
(2) An Economic Interpretation of the United
States Constitution(3) See Laski : The American democracy; Weaver :
Constitutional Law, Brown: Charles Beard and
the constitution; will is constitutional Law.
892 the concept of just compensation, the
amendment added a new clause (2A) as follows :"(2A) Where a law does not
provide for the transfer of the ownership or right to possession of, any
property to the State or to a corporation owned or control led by the State, it
shall not be deemed to provide for the compulsory acquisition or requisitioning
of property, notwithstanding that' it deprives any person of his
property." This narrowed the field in which compensation was payable.
In addition to this, clause (1) of Art. 31-A
was substituted and was deemed to be always substituted by a new clause which
provided:
"(1) Notwithstanding anything contained
in article 13, no law providing for(a) the acquisition by the State -of any
estate or of any rights therein or the extinguishment or modification of any
such rights, or (b) the taking over of the management of any property by the State
for a limited period either in the public interest 'or in order to secure the
proper management of the property, or (c) amalgamation of two or more
corporations either in the public interest or in order to secure the proper
management of any of the corporation, or (d) the extinguishment or modification
of any rights of 'managing agents secretaries and treasurers, managing
directors, directors or managers of corporations, or of any voting rights of
shareholders thereof, or (e) the extinguishment or modification of any rights
accruing by virtue of any agreement, lease or licence for the purpose of
searching for, or winning, any mineral or mineral oil, or the premature
termination or cancellation of any such agreement, lease or licence, shall be
deemed to be void on the ground that it is inconsistent with, or takes away or
abridges any of the rights conferred by Art. 14, article 19 or article 31
Provided that where such law is a law made by the Legislature of a State, the
provisions of this article shall not apply thereto unless such law, having been
reserved 893 for the consideration of the President, has received assent."
In clause (2)(a) after the word 'grant', the words "and in any State of
Madras and Travancore Cochin any, Janmam right" were inserted 'and deemed
always to have been inserted and in clause (2) (b) after the words
'tenure-holder' the words "raiyat, under raiyat" were inserted and
deemed always tohave been inserted. Once again the reach of the State towards
private property was made longer and curiously enough it was done
retrospectively from the time of the Constituent Assembly and so to speak, in
its name. As to the retrospective operation of these, Constitutional amendment.
I entertain considerable doubt... A Constituent Assembly makes a new
Constitution for itself. Parliament is not even a Constituent Assembly and to.
abridge fundamental rights in the name of the Constituent Assembly appears
anomalous. I am reminded of the conversation between apoleon and Abe . Sieyes,
the, great jurist whose ability to draw up one Constitution after another has
been recognised and none of whose efforts lasted for long. When Napoleon asked
him "what has survived ?" Abe Sieyes answered "I have
survived". I wonder if the Constituent Assembly will be able to say the
same thing What it had written or the, subject of property rights, appears to
have been written on water. The Fourth Amendment served to do away with the
distinction made by this Court between Arts. 19 and 31 and the theory of just
compensation. The Fourth Amendment has not been challenged before us. Nor was
it challenged at any time before. For the reasons for which I have declined to
consider the First Amendment I refrain from considering the validity of the
Fourth Amendment. It may, however, be stated here that if I was free to
consider it,, I would have found great difficulty in accepting that the
constitutional guarantee could be abridged in this way.
I may say here that the method I have
followed in not recon, sidering an amendment which has stood for a long time,
was also invoked by the Supreme Court of United: States in Leser v. Garnett(1).
A constitution works only because of universal recognition. This recognition
may. be voluntary or forced where people have lost liberty of speech. But the
acquiescence of the people is necessary for the working of the Constitution.
The examples of our neighbours, of Germany, of Rhodesia and others illustrates
the recognition of Constitutions by acquiescence.. It is obvious that it is
good sense and sound policy for the 'Courts to decline to take 'up an amendment
for consideration after a considerable lapse of time when it was not challenged
before, or was sustained on an earlier occasion after challenge.
(1) (1922) 258 U.S. 130.
894 It is necessary to pause here and see
what the property rights have become under the repeated and retrospective
amendments of the Constitution. I have already said that the Constitution
started with the concept of which, Grotius may' be said to be the author,
although his name is not particularly famous for theories of constitutional or
municipal laws. The socialistic tendencies which the amendments now manifest
take into consideration some later theories about the institution of property.
When theoriginal Art. 31 was moved by Pandit Jawaharlal Nehru, he had described
it as a compromise between various approaches to the question and said that it
did justice and equality not only to the individual but also to the community'
He accepted the principle of compensation but compensation as determined by the
Legislature and not the Judiciary. His words were "The law should do it.
Parliament should do it. There is no reference in this to any judiciary coming
into the picture. Much thought has been given to it and there has been much
debate as to where the judiciary comes in. Eminent lawyers have told us that on
a proper construction of this clause, normally speaking the judiciary should
not come in. Parliament fixes either the compensation itself or the principle
governing that compensation and they should not be challenged except for one
reason, where it is thought that there has been a gross abuse of the law,
where, in fact, there has been a fraud on the Constitution. Naturally the
judiciary comes in to see if there has been a fraud on the Constitution or
not."(1) He traced the evolution of property and observed that property
was becoming a question of credit, of monopolies, that there were two
approaches, the approach of the Individual and the approach of the community.
He expressed for the for protection of the indi vidual's rights.(2) The
attitude changed at the time of the First Amendment. Pandit Nehru propheised
that the basic problem would come before the House from time to, time. That it
has, there is no doubt, just as there is no doubt that each time the
individual's rights have suffered.
Of course, the growth of collectivist
theories have made elsewhere considerable inroads into the right of property.
In Russia there is no private ownership of.
land and even in the Federal Capital Territory of Australia, the ownership of
land is with the Crown and the individual can get a leasehold right only.
Justification for this is found in the fact that the State must benefit from
(1) Constituent Assemembly Debates Vol. IX pp. 1193-1195.
(2) Constituent Assembly Debates Vol. IX p.
1135.
895 the rise in the value of land. The
paucity of land and of dwelling houses have led to the control of urban
properties and creation of statutory tenancies. In our country a ceiling is put
on agricultural land held by an individual.
The Supreme Court, in spite of this, has not
frustrated any genuine legislation for agrarian reform. It has upheld the laws
by which the lands from latifundia have been distributed among the landless. It
seems that as the Constitutions of Peru, Brazil, Poland, Latvia, Lethuania and
Mexico contain provisions for such reforms, mainly without payment of
compensation, our Parliament has taken the same road. Of course, the modem
theory regards the institution of proper on a functional basis(1) which means
that property to be productive must be property distributed. As many writers
have said property is now a duty more than a right and ownership of property
entails a social obligation.
Although Duguit(2), who is ahead of others, thinks
that the institution of property has undergone a revolution, the rights of the
Individual are not quite gone, except where Communism is firmly entrenched. The
rights are qualified but property belongs still to the owner. The Seventeenth
Amendment, however, seems to take us far away, from even this qualified
concept, at least in so far as "estates" as defined by Art. 31-A.
This is the culmination of a process.
Previous to the Constitution (Seventeenth
Amendment) Act the Constitution (Seventh Amendment) Act, 1956 had given power
indirectly by altering entry No. 42 in List III. The entries may be read side
by side :
"42. (Before Amendment) (After
Amendment) Principles on which compensation for Acquisition and requisitioning,
of pro property acquired or requisitioned for perty. the purposes of the Union
or of a State or for any other public purpose is to be determined, and the form
and the manner in which such compensation is to be given." This removed
the last reference to compensation in respect of acquisition and requisition.
What this amendment began, the Constitution (Seventeenth Amendment) Act, 1964
achieved in full. The Fourth Amendment had added to the comprehensive
definition of 'right in relation to an estate, the rights of raiyats and
under-raiyats. This time the expression 'estate' in Art. 31 A was amended
retrospectively by a new definition which reads:
"the expression "estate"
shall, in relation to any local area, have the same meaning as that expression
or its local equivalent has in the existing law relating to (1) See G.W. Paton
: Text Book of Jurisprudence (1964) pp. 484-485.
(2) Transformations du droit prive.
896 land tenures in force in that area, and
shall also include(i) any jagir, inam or muafi or other similar grant and in
the States of Madras and Kerala, any janmam right;
(ii) any land held under ryotwari settlement;
(iii) any land held or let for purposes of
agriculture or for purposes ancillary thereto, including waste land, forest
land, land for pasture or sites of buildings and other structures occupied by
cultivators of land, agricultural labourers and village artisans," The
only saving of compensation is now to be found in the second proviso added to
clause (1) of the article which reads "Provided further that, where any law
makes any provision for the acquisition by the State of any estate. and where
any land comprised therein is held by a per-, son under his personal
cultivation, it shall not be lawful for the State to acquire any portion of
such land as is within the ceiling limit applicable to him under any law for.
the time being in force or any building or structure standing thereon or
appurtenant thereto, unless the law relating to the acquisition of such land,
building or structure, provides for payment of compensation at a rate which
shall not be less than the market value thereof." There is also the
provision for compensation introduced indirectly in an Explanation at the end
of the Ninth Schedule, in respect of the Rajasthan Tenancy Act, 1955. By this
explanation the provisions of this Tenancy Act in conflict with the proviso
last last quoted are declared to be void.
The sum total of this amendment is that
except for land within the ceiling,all other land can be acquired ed or rights
therein extinguished or modified without compensation and no. challenge to the
law can be made under Arts. 14, 19 or 31 of the Constitution. The same is also
true of the taking over: of 'the management of any property by the State for a
limited period either in the public interest or in order to secure the proper
management of the property, or the amalgamation of two or more companies, or
the extinguishment or modification of any rights of managing agents,,
secretaries, treasurers, managing directors, directors or managers, of corporations
or of any voting right, of shareholders thereof any rights by virtue of an),
agreement, lease, or licence for the purpose of searching for, or winning, any
mineral or mineral oil, or of the premature 897 termination. or cancellation of
any such agreement,lease or licence.
It will be noticed further that deprivation
of property of any person is not to be regarded as acquisition or requisition
unless the benefit of the transfer of the ownership or right to possession goes
to the State--or to a corporation owned or controlled by the State. Acquisition
or requisition in this limited sense alone requires that it should be for
public purpose and under authority of law which fixes the compensation or lays
down the principles on which and. the manner in which compensation is to be
determined. and given, and the adequacy of the compensation cannot be any
ground of attack. Further still acquisition of estates and of rights therein
and the taking over of property, amalgamation of corporations, extinguishment
or modification of rights in companies and mines may be made regardless of
Arts. 14, 19 and 31. In addition 64 State Acts are given special protection
from the courts regardless of therein contents which 'may be in derogation of
the Fundamental Rights.
This is the kind of amendment which has been
upheld in Sajjan Singh(1) case on the theory of the omnipotence of Art. 368.
The State had bound itself not to' enact any law in derogation of Fundamental
Rights. Is the Seventeenth Amendment a law ? To this question my answer is a
categoric yes. It is no answer to gay that this is an amendment and;
therefore; not a law, or that it is passed by
a special power of voting. It is the action of the State all the same. The
State had put restraints on itself in law making whether the laws were made
without Dr. within the Constitution.. it is also' no answer to say that this
Court in a Bench of five Judges on one, occasion and by a majority of 3 to 2 on
another, has said the,same thing. In a. matter of the interpretation of
the-Constitution this Court must,look at the functioning of the Constitution as
a whole.
The rules of res indicate and stare decisis
are not, always appropriate in interpreting a Constitution, particularly when
Art. 13(2) itself declares a law to be void. The sanctity of a former judgment
is for the matter then decided-. In Plessy v. Fergusson(2), Harlan, J. alone,
dissented against the "separate but equal doctrine uttering the memorable
words that there was no caste and that the Constitution of the United States
was 'colour blind. This dissent made some Southern Senators to oppose his
grandson (Mr. Justice John Marshall Harlan) in 1954. It took fiftyeight years
for the words of Harlan, J.'s lone dissent (8 to 1) to become, the law of the
united states at least in respect of segregation in the public schools [See
Brown v.
Board of Education(3)]. As Mark Twain (1)
(1965] 1 S. C. R. 933.
(2)163 U. S. 537.
(3) (1954) 347 U. S. 483.
898 said very truly-"Loyality to a
petrified opinion never yet broke a chain or freed a human soul" I am
apprehensive that the erosion of the right to property may be practised against
other Fundamental Rights. If a halt is to be called, we must declare the right
of Parliament to abridge or take away Fundamental Rights.
Small inroads lead to larger inroads and
become as habitual as before our freedom won The history of freedom is not only
how freedom is achieved but how it is preserved. I am of opinion that an
attempt to abridge or take away Fundamental Rights by a constituted Parliament
even through an amendment of the Constitution can be declared void. This Court
has the power and jurisdiction to make the declaration. I dissent from the
opposite view expressed in Sajjan Singh's(1) case and I overrule that decision.
It remains to consider what is the extent of
contravention.
Here I must make it clear that since the
First, Fourth and Seventh Amendments are not before me and I have not,
therefore, questioned them, I must start with the provisions of Arts. 31, 31-A,
31-B, List III and the Ninth Schedule as they were immediately preceding the
Seventeenth Amendment.
I have elsewhere given a summary of the
inroads made into property rights of individuals and Corporations by these
earlier amendments. By this amendment the definition of 'estate' was repeated
for the most part but was extended to include:
"(ii) any land held under ryotwari
settlement;
(iii) any land held or let for purposes
ancillary thereto, including waste land, forest land, land for pasture or sites
of buildings and other structures occupied by cultivators of land, agricultural
labourers and village artisans." Further reach of acquisition or
requisition without adequate compensation and without a challenge under Arts.
14, 19 and 31 has now been made possible. There is no kind of agricultural
estate or land which cannot be acquired by the State even though it pays an
illusory compensation. The only exception is the second proviso added to Art.
31-A(1) by which, lands within the ceiling limit applicable for the time being
to a person personally cultivating his land, may be acquired only on paying
compensation at a rate which shall not be less than the-market value. This may
prove: to be an illusory protection. The ceiling may be lowered by legislation.
The State may leave the person an owner in name and acquire all his. other
rights. The latter question did come before this Court in two cases-Ajit Singh
v. State of Punjab (2) (1) (1965] 1 & C. R. 933 (2) [1967] 2 S. C. R. 143.
899 and Bhagat Ram and Ors. v. State of Punjab,
and Ors. (1) decided on December 2, 1966. My brother Shelat and, I described
the device as a fraud upon this proviso but it is obvious that a law lowering
the ceiling to almost nothing cannot be declared a fraud on the Constitution.
In other words, the agricultural landholders hold land as tenants-atwill. To
achieve this a large number of Acts of the State Legislatures have been added
to the Ninth Schedule to bring them under the umbrella of Art. 31-B. This list
may grow.
In my opinion the extension of the definition
of 'estate' to include ryotwari and agricultural lands is an inroad into the
Fundamental Rights but it cannot be questioned in view of the existence of Art.
31-A(1) (a) as already amended.
The constitutional amendment is a law and
Art. 31 (I) permits the deprivation of property by authority of law.
The law may be made outside the Constitution
or within it.
The word 'law' in this clause includes both
ordinary law or an amendment of the Constitution. Since "no law providing
for the acquisition by the State of any estate or of any rights therein or the
extinguishment or modification of any such rights shall be deemed to be void on
the ground that it is inconsistent with, or takes away or abridges any of the
rights conferred by Art. 14, Art. 19 or Art. 31", the Seventeenth
Amendment when it gives a new definition of the word 'estate cannot be
questioned by reason of the Constitution as it exists. The new definition of
estate introduced by the amendment is beyond the reach of the courts not because
it is not law but because it is "law" and falls within that word in
Art. 31 (1) (2) (2-A) and Art. 31A(1). 1, therefore, sustain the new
definition, not on the erroneous reasoning in Sajjan Singh's case (2 ) but on
the true construction of the word 'law' as used in Arts. 13(2), 31(1)(2-A) and
31-A(1). The above reason applies a fortiori to the inclusion of the proviso
which preserves (for the time being) the notion of compensation for deprivation
of a cultural property. The proviso at least saves something.
It prevents the, agricultural lands below the
ceiling from being appropriated without payment of pro-per compensation.
It is clear,that the proviso at least cannot
be held to abridge or take away fundamental rights. In the result I uphold the
second section of the Constitution (Seventeenth Amendment) Act, 1964.
This brings me to the third section of the
Act. That does no more than add 44 State Acts to the Ninth Schedule. The object
of Art. 31-B, when it was enacted, was to save certain State Acts
notwithstanding judicial decision to the contrary. These Acts were already
protected by Art. 31.
One can with difficulty understand such a
provision. Now the Schedule is being used to (1) 11967] 2 S. C. R. 165.
(2) (1965) 1 S. C. R. 933.
900 give advance protection to legislation
which is known apprehended to derogate from the Fundamental Rights. The power
under Art. 368, whatever it may be, was given to amend the Constitution.
Giving. protection to statutes of State Legislatures which offend the Constitution
in its most fundamental part, can hardly merit the description amendment of the
Constitution in fact in so cases it is not even known whether the statues in
question stand in need of such aid.
The intent is to silence the courts and not
to amend the Constitution. If these Acts were', not included in the Schedule
they would have to face the Fundamental Rights and rely on Arts. 31 and 31-A to
save them. By this device protection far in excess of 'these articles is
afforded to them. This in my judgment is not a matter of amendment at all. The
power which is given is for the specific purpose of amending the Constitution
and not to confer validity on State Acts against the rest of the Constitution.
If the President's assent did not do this, no more would this section. I
consider s.. 3 of the Act., to be invalid as an illegitimate exercise of the
powers . of amendment however generous. Ours is the only Constitution in the
world which carries a long list of ordinary laws which it protects against
itself,. In the result I declare s. 3 to be ultra vires the amending process.
As stated by me in Sajjan Singh's case(1)
Art. 368 outlines process, which if followed strictly results in the amendment
of the Constitution. The article gives power to no particular person or
persons. All the named authorities have to act according to the letter of the
article to achieve the result. The procedure of, amendment, if it can be called
a 'power at all is a legislative power but it is sui generi and outside the
three lists in Schedule 7 of the Constitution. 'It does 'not' have to depend.
upon any entry,in the lusts.
Ordinarily there would-be no limit to the
extent of the , amendatory legislation but. the Constitution itself makes
distinctions. It states three methods and places certain bars. For some
amendments an ordinary, majority fs sufficient; for some others 'a 2/3rd
majority of the, members present and voting with a majority of the total
members, in each House is necessary: and for some others in addition to the
second requirement, ratification by at least one,half of the legislatures of
the States must be forthcoming. Besides these methods, Art. 13(2) puts an
embargo on the legislative power of the State and consequently upon the
agencies of the State. By its means the boundaries of legislative action of any
of including legislation to amend the Constitution have been marked out.
(1) [1965]1 S.C.R 933.
901 I have attempted to show hem that under
our Constitution revolution is not the only alternative to change of Constitution
under Art. 368. A Constitution can. be changed by consent or, revolution Rodee,
Anderson and Christol (1) have shown the sovereignty of the People is either
electoral or constituent. When the People elect the Parliament and the
Legislatures they exercise their electoral sovereignty. I includes some
constituent sovereignty also but only in so far as conceded. The remaining
constituent sovereignty which is contained in the Preamble and Part III is in
abeyance because of the curb placed by the People on the state under Art.
13(2). It is this power which can be reproduced. I have indicated the method.
Watson(2) quoting AmesOn Amendments p. 1 note 2) points out that the idea that
provision should be made in the instrument of Government itself for the method
of its amendment is peculiarly American. But even in the Constitution of the
United States of America some matters were kept away from the amendatory
process Other temporarily or permanently. Our Constitution has done the same .
Our Constitution provides for minorities, religions, socially and educationally
backward peoples, for ameliorating the condition of depressed classes, for
removing class distinctions, titles, etc. This reservation was made so that in
the words of Madison(3), men of factious tempers, of local prejudices, or
sinister designs may not by intrigue, by corruption, or other means , first
obtain the suffrages and then betray the interests of the people. It was to
plug the loophole such as existed in s. 48 of the Weimar Constitution( 4) that
Art. 13 (2) was. adopted. of course, as. Story('') says, an amendment process
is a safety valve to, let off all temporary effervescence and excitement, as an
effective instrument to control and adjust the Movements of the machinery when
out of order or in danger of self-d tion but is not an open valve to let, out'
even that which was intended to be retained. In the words of Wheare(6) the
people or a Constituent Assembly acting on their behalf, has authority to enact
a Constitution and by the same token a portion of-the Constitution placed
outside the-amenditory process by one Constituent body can only be amended by
another Constituent body. In the Commonwealth of, Australia Act the provisions
of the last Paragraph of s. 128 have been regarded as, mandatory, andheld to be
clear limitations of the power of amendment. Dr. Jethro Brown considered that
the amendment of the paragraph was logically impossible even by a two step
amendment. Similarly, s. 105A has been judicially (1) Introduction to Political
Science, p. 32 et seq.
(2) Constitution" Its History,
Application and Construction Vol.II (1910) p. 1301.
(3) Federalist No. 10.
(4) See Louis L. Snyder: The Weimar
Constitution, p. 42 et seq.
(5) Commentaries on the Constitution of the
United States (I 833) Vol. II.
(6) K. C. Wheare: Modern Constitutions, p.
78.
sup Cl/67-12 902 considered in the Garnishee
case(-') to be an exception to the power of amendment in s. 128 although
Wynes(2) does not agree. I prefer the judicial view to that of Wynes. The same
position obtains under our Constitution in Art. 35 where the opening words, are
more than a non-obstante clause. They exclude Art. 368 and even amendment of
that article under the proviso. It is, therefore, a grave error to think of
Art. 368 as a code ;Dr as omnicompetent. It is the duty of this Court to find
the limits which the Constitution has set on the amendatory power and to
enforce those limits. This is what I have attempted to do in this judgment.
My conclusions are (i) that the Fundamental
Rights are outside the amendatory process if the amendment seeks to abridge or
take away any of the rights;
(ii) that Sankari Prasad's case (and Sajjan
Singh's case which followed it) conceded the power of amendment over Part III
of the Constitution on an erroneous view of Arts.
13(2) and 368;
(iii) that the First, Fourth and Seventh
Amendments being part of the Constitution by acquiescence for a long time,
cannot now be challenged and they contain authority for the Seventeenth
Amendment;
(iv) that this Court having now laid down
that Fundamental Rights cannot be abridged or taken away by the exercise of
amendatory process in Art. 368, any further inroad into these rights as they
exist today will be illegal and unconstitutional unless it complies with Part
III in general and Art.
13(2) in particular, (v) that for abridging
or taking away Fundamental Rights, a Constituent body will have to be,
convoked; and (vi) that the two impugned Acts, namely, the Punjab Security of
Land Tenures Act, 1953 (X of 1953) and the Mysore Land Reforms Act, 1961 (X of
1962) as amended by act XIV of 1965 are valid under the Constitution not
because they are included in schedule 9 of the Constitution but because the,
are protected by Art. 31-A, and the President's assent.
(1) 46 C. L. R. 155.
(2) Legislative, Executive and Judicial
Powers in Australia pp. 695-698.
903 In view of my decision the several petit
ions will be dismissed, but without costs. The State Acts Nos. 21-64 in the
Ninth Schedule will have to be tested under Part HI with such protection as
Arts. 31 and 31 A give to them.
Before parting with this case I only hope
that the Fundamental Rights will be able to withstand the pressure of textual
readings by "the depth and toughness of their roots".
Bachawat, J The constitutionality of the
Constitution First, Fourth and Seventeenth Amendment Acts is challenged on the
.
ground that the fundamental rights conferred
by Part HI are inviolable and immune from amendment. It is said that art.
368 does not give any power of amendment and,
in any event, the amending power is limited expressly by art. 13(2) and
impliedly by the language of art. 368 and other articles as also the preamble.
It is then said that the power of amendment is abused and should be subject to
restrictions.
The Acts are attacked also on the ground that
they made changes in arts. 226 and 245 and such changes could not be made
without complying with the proviso to art. 368.
Article 31-B is subjected to attack on
several other grounds.
The constitutionality of the First Amendment
was upheld in Sri Sankari Prasad Singh Deo v. Union, of India and State of
Bihar(1), and that of the Seventeenth amendment, in Sajjan Singh is that these
cases were Part XX of the Constitution specifically provides for its amendment.
It consists of a single article-. Part XXis as follows "PART XX.
Amendment of the Constitution Procedure for
amendment of the Constitution 368. An amendment of this Constitution may be
initiated only by the introduction of a Bill for the purpose in either House of
Parliament, and when the Bill is passed in each House by a majority of the
total membership of that House and by a majority of not less than two-thirds of
the members of that House present and voting, it shall be presented to the
President for his assent and upon such assent being given to the Bill the
Constitution shall stand amended in accordance with the terms of the Bill :
Provided that if such amendment seeks to make
any change in (a) article 54. article 55, article 73, article 162 or (1) [1952]
S.C.R. 89.
(2) [1965] 1 S.C.R. 933.
1196712 S.C.IL 904 (b) Chapter IV of Part V,
Chapter V of Part VI, or Chapter 1 of Part XI, or (c) any of the Lists in the
Seventh Schedule, or (d) the representation of States in Parliament, or (e) the
provisions of this article, the amendment shall also require to be ratified by
the Legislatures of not less than one-half of the States by resolutions to that
effect passed by those Legislatures before the Bill making provision for such
amendment is presented to the President for assent." The contention that
article 368 prescribes only the procedure of amendment cannot be accepted. The
article not only prescribes the procedure but also gives the power of
amendment. If the procedure of art.368 is followed, the Constitution
"shall stand amended" in accordance with the terms of the bill. It is
because the power to amend is given by the article that the Constitution stands
amended.
The proviso is enacted on the assumption that
the several articles mentioned in it are amendable. The object of the proviso
is to lay down a stricter procedure for amendment of the articles which would
otherwise have been amendable under the easier procedure of the main part.
There is no other provision in the Constitution under which these articles can
be amended.
Articles 4, 169, Fifth Schedule Part D, and
Sixth Schedule Para 21 empower the Parliament to. pass laws amending the
provisions of the First, Fourth, Fifth and Sixth Schedules and making
amendments of the Constitution consequential on the abolition or creation of
the legislative councils in States, and by express provision no such law is
deemed to be an amendment of the Constitution for the purposes of art.
368. All other provisions of the Constitution
can be amended by recourse to art. 368 only. No other article confers the power
of amending the Constitution.
Some articles are expressed to continue until
provision is made by law [see articles 59(3), 65(3), 73(2), 97, 98(3), 106,
135, 142(1), 148(3), 149, 171(2), 186, 187(3), 189(3), 194(3), 195, 221(2),
283(1) and (2), 285, 313, 345, 372(1), 373]. Some articles continue unless
provision is made otherwise by law [see articles 120(2), 133(3), 210(2) and
some continue save as otherwise provided by law [see articles 239(1), 287].
Some articles are subject to the provisions of any law to be made [see articles
137, 146(2), 225, 229(2), 241(3), 300(1), 309], and some are expressed not to
derogate from the power of making laws [see articles 5 to 11, 289(2)]. All
these articles are transitory in nature and cease to operate when provision is
made by law on the subject. None of them can be regarded as conferring 905 the
power of 'amendment of the Constitution. Most of articles continue until
provision is made by law made by the Parliament. But some of them continue
until or unless provision is made by the State Legislature (see articles 189
(3), 194 (3), 195, 210(2), 229(2), 300(1), 345) or by the appropriate
legislature (see articles 225, 241(3)); these articles do not confer a power of
amendment, for the State legislature cannot amend the Constitution. Many of the
above-mentioned articles and also other articles (see articles 22(7), 32(3), 33
to 35, 139,140, 239A, 241, 245 to 250, 252, 253, 258(2), 286(2), 302, 307,
315(2), 327, 369 delegate powers of making laws to the legislature. None of
these articles gives the power of amending the Constitution.
It is said that art. 248 and List 1 item 97
of the 7th Schedule read with art. 246 give the Parliament the power of
amending the Constitution. This argument does not bear scrutiny. Art. 248 and
List I item 97 vest the residual power of legislation in the Parliament. Like
other powers of legislation, the residual power of the Parliament to make laws
is by virtue of art. 245 subject to the provisions of the Constitution. No law
made under the residual power can derogate from the Constitution or amend it.
If such a law purports to amend the Constitution, it will 'be void. Under the
residual power of legislation, the Parliament has no power to make any law with
respect to any matter enumerated in Lists II and III of the 7th Schedule but
under art. 368 even Lists II and III can be amended. The procedure for
constitutional amendments under art. 368 is different from the legislative
procedure for passing laws under the residual power of legislation. If a
constitutional amendment could be made by recourse to the residual power of
legislation and the ordinary legislative procedure, art. 368 would be
meaningless. The power of amending the Constitution is to be found in art. 368
and not in art. 248 and List I item 97. Like other Constitutions, our
Constitution makes express provisions for amending the Constitution.
The heading of art. 368 shows that it is a
provision for amendment of the Constitution, the marginal note refers to the
procedure for amendment and the body shows that if the procedure is followed,
the Constitution shall stand amended by the power of the article.
Chapter VIII of the Australian Constitution
consists of a single section (S. 128). The heading is "Alteration of the
Constitution". The marginal note is "Mode of altering the
Constitution". The body lays down the procedure for alteration. The
opening words are : "This Constitution shall not be altered except in the
following manner".
Nobody has doubted that the section gives the
power of amending the Constitution. Wynes in his book on Legislative Executive
and Judicial Powers in Australia, third edition, 906 p. 695, stated "The
power, of amendment extends to alteration of this Constitution' which includes
S. 128 itself. It is true that S. 128 is negative in form, but the power is
impled by the terms of the section." Article 5 of the United States
Constitution provides that a proposal for amendment of the constitution by the
Congress on being ratified by the three-fourth of the states "shall be
valid to all intents and purposes as part of this Constitution". The
accepted view is that "power to amend the Constitution was reserved by
article 5", Per Van Devanter, J, in Rhode Island v. Palmer(1): Art .368
uses stronger words. On the passing of the bill for amendment under art. 368,
"the Constitution shall stand amended in accordance with the terms of the
bill".
Article 368 gives the power of amending
"this-Constitution".
This Constitution means any of the provisions
of the Constitution. No limitation on the amending power can be gathered from
the language of this article. Unless this power is restricted by some ,other
provision of the Constitution, each and every part of the Constitution may be
amended under art. 368. AR the articles mentioned in the proviso are
necessarily within this amending power. From time to time major amendments have
been made in the articles mentioned in the proviso (see articles 80 to 82, 124
(2A),131,214,217(3),222,(k2) 224A,226(IA) 230,231,241 and Seventh Schedule) and
other articles (see articles 1, 3, 66, 71, 85, 153. 158, 170, 174, 239, 239A,
240, 258A, 2,69, 280, 286, 290A, 291, 298, 305, 311, 316, 350A, 350B, 371,
371A, 372A, 376, 379 to 391, the first third and fourth schedules), and minor
amendments have been made in innumerable articles. No one has doubted so far
that these articles are amendable. Part III is a part of the Constitution and
is equally amendable.
It is argued that a Constitution Amendment
Act.is a law and therefore the power of amendment given by art. 368 is limited
by art. 13(2)., Art. 13(2) is in these terms:-"13(1).......................................
(2) The State shall not make any law which
takes away or abridges the tights conferred by this Part and any law made in
contravention of this clause shall, to the extent of the contravention, be
void." Now art. 3 68 gives, the power of amending each and every provision
of the Constitution Art. 13 (2) is a part of the Constitution and is within the
reach of the amending power.
In other words art 13 (2) is subject to the
overriding power of an. 368 and is controlled by it. Art. 368 is not controlled
by art. 13 (2) and the (1) 253 U.S. 350 : 64 LE.d. 946.
907 prohibitory injunction in art. 13(2) is
not directed against the amending power Looked at from this broad angle, art.
13 (2) does not forbid the making of a constitutional amendment abridaing or
taking away any right confesed by Part III.
Let us now view the matter from a narrower
angle. The contention is that a constitutional amendment under art. 368 is a
law within the meaning of art. 13. 1 am inclined to think that this narrow
contention must also be rejected.
In art. 13 unless the context otherwise
provides 'law' includes any ordinance, order, bye-law, rule, regulation,
notification, custom or usage having in the territory of India the force of law
[article 13(3).(a)]. The inclusive definition of law in art. 13 (3) (c) neither
expressly excludes nor expressly includes the Constitution or a constitutional
amendment.
Now the term law' in its widest and generic
sense includes the Constitution and a constitutional amendment. But in the
constitution this term is employed to designate an ordinary statute or
legislative act in contradistinction to the Constitution or a constitutional
amendment. The Constitution is the basic law providing the framework of
government and creating the organs for the making of the laws. The distinction
between the Constitution and the laws is so fundamental that the Constitution
is not regarded as a law or a legislative act. The Constitution means the
Constitution as amended. An amendment made in conformity with art. 368 is a
part of the. Constitution and is likewise not a law.
The basic theory of our Constitution is that
it cannot be changed by a law or legislative Act. It is be-cause special
provision is made by articles 4, 169, Fifth Schedule Part D and Sixth Schedule
para 21 that some parts of the Constitution are amendable by ordinary laws. But
by express provision no such law is deemed to be a constitutional amendment.
Save as express.1y provided in articles 4, 169, Fifth Schedule Part D and Sixth
Schedule para 21, no law can amend the Constitution, and a law which purports
to make such an amendment is void.
In Marbury v. Madison(1), Marshall, C.J.,
said:
"It is a proposition too plain to be
contested, that the Constitution controls any legislative Act repugnant to it;
or, that the legislature may alter the Constitution by an ordinary Act.
Between these alternatives there is no middle
ground. The Constitution is either a superior paramount law, unchangeable by
ordinary means, or it is on a level with (1) [1803] 1 Cranch 137,177:. 2 L. Ed.
60, 73.
908 Ordinary legislative Acts, and, like
other Acts, is alterable when the legislature shall please to alter it. If the
former part of the alternative be true, then a legislative Act contrary to the
Constitution is not law; if the, latter part be true, then written
constitutions are absurd attempts, on the part of the people, to limit a power
in its own nature illimitable.
Certainly all those who have framed written
constitutions contemplate them as forming the fundamental and paramount law of
the nation, and, consequently, the theory of every such government must be,
that an Act of the Legislature, repugnant to the Constitution, is void. This
theory is essentially attached to a written constitution, and is consequently
to be considered, by this court, as one of the fundamental principles of our
society." It is because a Constitution Amendment Act can amend the
Constitution and is not a law that art. 368 avoids all reference to law making
by the Parliament. As soon as a bill is passed in conformity with art. 368 the
Constitution stands amended in accordance with the terms of the bill.
The power of amending the Constitution is not
an ordinary law making power. It is to be found in art. 368 and not in articles
245, 246 and 248 and the Seventh Schedule.
Nor is the procedure for amending the
Constitution under art. 368 an ordinary law making procedure. The common
feature of the amending process under art, 368 and the legislative procedure is
that a bill must be passed by each House of Parliament and assented to by the
President. In other respects the amending process under art. 368 is very
different from the ordinary legislative proms. A constitution amendment Act
must be initiated by a bill introduced for that purpose in either House of
Parliament.
The bill must be passed in each House by not
less than two thirds of the members present and voting, the requisite quorum in
each House being a majority of its total membership; and in cases coming under
the proviso, the amendment must be ratified by the legislature of not less than
one half of the States. Upon the bill so passed being assented to by the
President, the Constitution stands.
amended in accordance with the terms of the
bill. The ordinary legislative process is much easier. A bill initiating a law
may be passed by a majority of the members present and voting at a sitting of
each House or at a joint sitting of the Houses, the quorum for the meeting of
either House being one tenth of the total number of members of the House. The
bill so passed on being assented to by the President becomes a law. A bill
though passed by all the members of both Houses cannot take effect as a 909
Constitution amendment Act unless it is initiated for the express purpose of
amending the Constitution.
The essence of ,a written Constitution is
that it cannot be changed by an ordinary law. But most written Constitutions
Provide for their organic growth by constitutional amendments.
The main method of constitutional amendments
are (1) by the ordinary legislature but under certain restrictions, (2) by the
people through areferendum, (3) by a majority of all the units of a Federal
State; (4) by a special convocation, see C.F. strong Modem Political
institutions, 5th Edition, pp. 1334,146. Our Constitution hag by article 368
chosen the first and a combination of the first and the third methods.
The special attributes of constitutional
amendment under art. 368 indicate that it is not a law or a legislative act.
Moreover it will be seen presently that the Constitution makers could not have
intended that the term "law" in art. 13 (2) would include a constitutional
amendment under art. 368.
If a constitutional amendment creating a new
fundamental right and incorporating it in Part III were a law, it would not be
open to the.
parliament by a subsequent constitution to
abrogate the new fundamental right for such an amendment would be repugnant to
Part ]III.
Bit the conclusion is absurd for. the body
which created the right can surely take it away by the same process.
Shri A. K. Sen relied upon a decision of the
Oklahoma Supreme Court in Riley v. Carter(1) where it was held that for some
purposes the Constitution of a State was one of the laws of the State. But even
in America, the term "law' does not ordinary include theConstitution or a
constitutional amendment in this connection, I will read the following passage
in Corpus Juris Secundum, Vol, XVI Title Constitutional Law Art. 1, P. 20:
.lm15 "The term 'constitution' is
ordinarily employed to designate the organic law in contradistinction to the
term law, which is generally used to designate statutes Or legislative
enactments. Accordingly the term 'law.' under this distinction does not include
a constitutional amendment. However, the term "law' may, in accordance
with the context in which it is used, comprehend or included the constitution or
a constitutional provision or amendment. A statute and a constitution, although
of unequal dignity,, are both 'laws', and rest on the will of the people."
(1) 88 A:A.L.R. 1008.
910 In our Constitution, the expression
"law" does not include either the constitution or a constitutional
amendment. For all these reasons we must hold that a constitutional amendment
under art. 368 is not a law within the meaning of art. 13 (2).
I find no conflict between articles 13(2) and
368. The two articles operate in different fields. Art. 13(2) operates on laws;
it makes no express exception regarding a constitutional amendment, because a
constitutional amendment is not a law and is outside its purview. Art. 368
occupies the field of constitutional amendments. It does not particularly refer
to the, articles in Part III and many other articles, but on its true
construction it gives the power of amending each and every provision of the
Constitution and necessarily takes in Part III. Moreover, art. 368 gives the
power of amending itself, and if express power for amending the provisions of
Part III were needed, such a power could be taken by an amendment of the
article.
It is said that the non-obstante clause in
art. 35 shows that the article is not amendable. No one has amended art.
35 and the point does not arise. Moreover,
the non-obstante clause is to be found in articles 258(1), 364, 369, 370 and
371A. No one has suggested that these articles are not amendable.
The next contention is that there are implied
limitations on the amending power. It is said that apart from art. 13 (2) there
are expressions in Part III which indicate that the amending power ,cannot
touch Part III. Part III is headed " fundamental rights". The right
to move the Supreme Court for enforcement of the rights conferred by this Part
is guaranteed by art. 32 and cannot be suspended except as otherwise provided
for by the Constitution (art. 32(4)). It is said that the terms
"fundamental" and "guarantee" indicate that the rights conferred
by Part HI are not amendable. The argument overlooks the dynamic character of
the Constitution. While the Constitution is static, it is the fundamental law
of the country, the rights conferred by Part III are, fundamental, the right
under art. 32 is guaranteed, and the principles of State policy enshrined in
Part IV are fundamental 'm the governance of the country.
But the Constitution is never at rest; it
changes with the progress of time. Art. 368 provides the means for the dynamic
changes in the Constitution. The scale cf values embodied in Parts III and IV
is not immortal. Parts III and IV being parts of the Constitution are not
immune from amendment under art. 368.
Demands for safeguards of the rights embodied
in Part III and IV may be traced to the Constitution of India Bill 1895, the
Congress Resolutions between 1917 and 1919, Mrs.
Beasan's Commonwealth of India Bill of 1925,
the Report of the Nehru Committee set up under the Congress Resolution in 1927,
the Congress 911 Resolution of March. 1931 and the Sapru Report of 1945. The
American bill of rights,the constitutions of other countries the declaration of
human rights by the United Nations and other declarations and charters gave
impetus to the demand.
In this background the Constituent Assembly
embodied in preamble to the Constitution the resolution to secure to all
citizens social, economic and political justice, liberty of thought,
expression, belief, faith and worship, equality of status and opportunity and
fraternity assuring the dignity of the individual and the unity of the nation
and incorporated safeguards as to some human rights in Parts III and IV of the
Constitution after separating them into two parts on the Irish model. Part III
contains the passive obligations of the State. It enshrines the right of life,
personal liberty, expression, assembly, movement, residence, avocation,
property, culture and education, constitutional remedies, and protection
against exploitation and obnoxious penal laws. The State shall not deny these
rights save as provided in the Constitution. Part IV contains the active
obligations of the State. The State shall secure a social order in which
social, economic and political justice shall inform all the institutions of
national life. Wealth and its source of production shall not be concentrated in
the hands of the few but shall be distributed so as to subserve the common
good, and there shall be adequate means of livelihood for all and equal pay for
equal work. The State shall endeavour to secure the health and strength of workers,
the right to work, to education and to assistance in cases of want, just and
humane conditions of work, a living wage for workers, a uniform civil code,
free and compulsory education for children. The State shall take steps to
organize village panchayats, promote the educational and economic interests of
the weaker sections of the people, raise the level of nutrition and standard of
living, improve public health. organize agricultural and animal husbandry
separate the judiciary from executive and promote international peace and
security.
The active obligations of the State under
Part IV are not justiciable. If a law made by the State in accordance with the
fundamental directives of Part IV comes in conflict with the fundamental rights
embodied in Part II the law to the extent of repugnancy is void. Soon after the
Constitution came into force, it became apparent that laws for agrarian and
other reforms for implementing the directives of Part IV were liable to be
struck down as they infringed the provisions of Part III. From time to time
constitutional amendments were proposed with the professed object of validating
these laws, superseding certain judicial interpretations of the Constitution
and curing defects in the original Constitution. The First, Fourth, Sixteenth
and Seventeenth Amendments made important changes in the fundamental rights.
The First amendment introduced cl. (4) in art. 15 enabling the State to make
special provisions for the benefit of the socially and 912 educationally
backward class of citizens, the,scheduled castes and the scheduled tribes in
derogation of articles 15 and 29,(2) with a view to implement art. 46 and to
supersede the decision in State of Madras v. Champakam(1), substituted a new
cl. (2) in art. 19 with retrospective effect chiefly with a view to be in
public order within the permissible restrictions and to supersede the decisions
in Romesh Thappar v. State of Madras('), Brij Bhushan v. State of Delhi(-'),,
amended cl. (6) of art. 19 with a view to free state trading monopoly from the
test of reasonable ness and to supersede the decision in Moti Lal v. Government
of State of Uttar Pradesh(). Under the stress of the First amendment it is now
suggested that Champakam's case('), Romesh Thappar's case(') and Motilal's(4) case
were wrongly decided, and the amendments of articles 15 and 19 were in harmony
with the original Constitution and made no real change in it. It is to be,
noticed however that before the First amendment no attempt was made to overrule
these cases, and but for the amendments, these judicial interpretations of the
Constitution would have continued to be the law of the land. The Zamindari
Abolition Acts were the subject of bitter attack by the zamindars. The Bihar
Act though protected by cl. 6 of art. 31 from attack under art. 31 was struck
down as violative of art. 14 by the Patna High Court (see the State of Bihar v.
Maharajadhiraj Sri Kameshwar Singh(5), while the Uttar Pradesh Act (see Raja
Surya Pal Singh v. The State. of U.P.) (6) and the Madhya Pradesh Act (see
Visweshwar Rao v. State.of Madhya Pradesh (7), though upheld by the High Courts
were under challenge in this Court. The First amendment therefore introduced
art. 31A, 31B and the Ninth Schedule with a view to give effect to the policy
of agrarian reforms, to secure distribution of large blocks of land in the
hands of the zamindars in conformity with art. 39, and to immunize specially 13
State Acts form attack under Part Ill. The validity of the First Amendment was
upheld in Sri Sankari Prasad Singh Deo's case(8). The Fourth amendment changed
art. 31(2) with a view to supersede the decision in State of West Bengal v.
Bela Banerjee(9) and to provide that the adequacy of compensation for property
compulsorily acquired would not be justiciable, inserted Cl.
(2A) in art. 31 with a view to supersede the
decisions in the State of West Bengal v. Subodh Gopal Bose("), Dwarka Das
Shrinivas v. Sholapur Spinning and Weaving Co., Ltd.,("), (1) [1951]
S.C.R. 525.
(2) [1950] S.C.R, 605.
(3) [1952] S.C.R. 654.
(4) I.L.R. [1951] 1 All. 269.
(5) [1952] S.C.R. 389 (A.I.R. 1951 Pat. 91).
(6) (1952] S.C.R. 1056 (A.I.R. 1961).
(7) [1952] S.C.R. 1020. All. 674.) (8) [1952]
S.C.R. 89. (9) [1954] S.C.R. 558.
(10) 11954] S.C.R. 587.(11) [1954] S.C.R.
674.
913 Saghir Ahmad v. The State of Uttar
Pradesh,(1) and to make it clear that clauses (1) and (2) of art. 31 relate to
different subject' matters and a deprivation of property short of transference
of ownership or right to possession to the State should not be treated as
compulsory acquisition of property. The Fourth amendment also amended art. 31A
with a view to protect certain laws other than agrarian laws and to give effect
to the policy of fixing ceiling limits on land holdings and included seven more
Acts in the Ninth Schedule.
One of the Acts (item 17) though upheld in
Jupiter General Insurance Co. v. Rajgopalan(2) was the subject of criticism in
Dwarka Das's case (3 ) . The Sixteenth amendment amended clauses (2), (3) and
(4) of art. 19 to enable the imposition of reasonable restrictions in the
interest of the sovereignty and integrity of India. The Seventeenth amendment
amended the definition of estate in art. 31A with a view to supersede the
decisions in Karimbil Kunhikoman v.
State of Kerala (4 ) and A. P. Krishnaswami
Naidu v. State of Madras(') and added a proviso to art. 31A and included 44
more Acts in the Ninth Schedule, as some of the Acts had been struck down as
unconstitutional. The validity of the Seventeenth amendment was upheld in
Sajjan Singh's case(').
Since 1951, numerous decisions of this Court
have recognised the validity of the First, Fourth and Seventeenth amendments.
If the rights conferred by Part III cannot be abridged or taken away by
constitutional amendments, all these amendments would be invalid. The
Constitution makers could not have intended that the rights conferred by Part
TIT could not be altered for giving effect to the policy of Part TV. Nor was it
intended that defects in Part III could not be cured or that possible errors in
judicial interpretations of Part III could not be rectified by constitutional
amendments.
There are, other indications in the
Constitution that the fundamental rights are not intended to be inviolable.
Some of the articles make express provision for abridgement of some of the
fundamental rights by law (see articles 16(3), 19(1) to (6), 22(3), 23(2),
25(2), 28(2), 31(4) to (6), 33, 34). Articles 358 and 359 enable the suspension
of fundamental rights during emergency. Likewise, art. 368 enables amendment of
the Constitution including all the provisions of Part Ill.
It is argued that the preamble secures the
liberties grouped together in Part III and as the preamble cannot be amended,
Part III is not amendable. The argument overlooks that the preamble is mirrored
in the entire Constitution., If the rest of the Constitution is amendable, Part
III cannot stand on a higher (1) [1954) S.C.R. 1218.
(3) [1954] S.C.R. 674,706.
(5) [1964] 7 S.C.R. 82.
(2) A.I.R. 1952 Pun. 9.
(4) [1962] Supp. I S.C.R. 829.
(6) [1965] 1 S.C.R. 933.
914 control the unambiguous language of the
articles of the Constitution, see' Wynes, Legislative Executive and Judicial
Powers in Australia third edition, pp. 694-5; in Re Berubari Union &
Exchange of Enclaves("). The last case decided that the Parliament can
under art. 368 amend art. 1 of the Constitution so as to enable the cession of
a part of the national territory to a foreign power, The Court brushed aside
the argument that "in the transfer of the areas of Berubari to Pakistan
the fundamental rights of thousands of persons are involved." The case is
an authority for the proposition that the Parliament can lawfully make a constitutional
amendment under art. 368 authorising cession of a part of the national
territory and thereby destroying the fundamental rights of the citizens of the
Effected territory, and this power under art. 368 is not limited by the
preamble.
It is next argued that the people of India in
exercise of their sovereign power have placed the fundamental rights beyond the
reach of the amending power. Reliance is place on the following passage in the
judgment of Patanjali Sastri, J., in A. K. Gopalan V. The State of Madras(2):
"There can be no doubt that,the people
of India have, in exercise of their sovereign will as expressed in the
Preamble, adopted the democratic ideal which assures to the citizen the dignity
of the, individual and other cherished human values as a means to the full
evolution and expression of his personality, and in delegating to the
Legislature the executive and the Judiciary their respective powers in the
Constitution, reserved to themselves certain fundamental rights, socalled, I
apprehend, because they have been retained by the people and made, paramount to
the delegated powers, as in the American Model." I find nothing in the
passage contrary to the view unequivocally expressed by the same learned Judge
in Sri Sankari Prasad Singh Deo's(3) case that the fundamental rights are
amendable. The power to frame the Constitution was vested in the Constituent
Assembly by s. 8 (1 ) of the Indian Independence Act, 1947. 'The Constitution
though legal in its origin was revolutionary in character and accordingly the
Constituent Assembly exercised its powers of framing the Constitution in the
name of the people. The objective resolution of the Assembly passed on January
22, 1947 (1) [1960] 3 S.C.R. 250,261-2,281 (2)[1950] S.C.R. 88, 98.
(3) (1952] S.C.R. 89.
915 solemnly declared that all power and
authority of sovereign independent India, its constituent parts, and organs and
the Government were derived from the people. The preamble to the Constitution
declares that the people of India adopts, enacts and gives to themselves the
Constitution. In form and in substance the Constitution emanates from the people.
By the Constitution. the people constituted
themselves into a republic. Under the republic all public power is derived from
the people and is exercised by functionaries chosen either directly or
'indirectly by the people. The Parliament can exercise only such powers as are
delegated to it under the Constitution. The people acting through the
Constituent Assembly reserved for themselves certain rights and liberties and
ordained that they shall not be curtailed by ordinary legislation. But the
people by the same Constitution also authorised the Parliament to make
amendments to, the Constitution. In the exercise of the amending power the
Parliament has ample authority to abridge or take away the fundamental rights
under Part III.
It is urged that the word 'amend' imposes the
limitation that an amendment must be an improvement of the Constitution.
Reliance is placed on the dictum in Livermore v. E. C. Waite(1): "On, the
other hand, the significance of the term 'amendment' implies such an addition
or change within the lines of the original instrument as will effect an
improvement, or better carry out the purpose for which it was framed." Now
an attack on the eighteenth amendment of the U.S. Constitution based on this
passage was brushed aside by the U.S. Supreme Court in the decision in the
National Prohibition(2) case. The decision totally negatived the contention
that "an amendment must be confined in its scope to, an alteration or
improvement of that which is already contained in the Constitution and cannot
change its basic structure, include new grants of power to the Federal
Government nor relinquish, in the State those which already have been granted
to it", see Cooley on Constitutional Law, Chapter III Art. 5, pp. 46 &
47. 1 may also read a passage from Corpus Juris Secundum Vol. XVI, title
'Constitutional Law, p. 26 thus : "The term 'amendment a-, used in the
constitutional article giving Congress a power of proposal includes additions
to, as well as corrections of, matters. already treated, and there is nothing
there which suggests that it is used in a restricted sense." Article 368
indicates that the term "amend" means "change".
The proviso is expressed to apply to
amendments which seek to make any "change" in certain articles. The
main part of art. 368 (1) 102 Cal. 11 3-25 L.R.A. 312.
(2) Rhode Island v. Palmer-253 U.S. 350 : 64
L. ed. 947, 960, 978.
916 thus gives the power to amend or to make
changes in the Constitution. A change is not necessarily an unprovement.
Normally the change is made with the object
of making an improvement, but the experiment may fail to achieve the purpose.
Even the plain dictionary meaning of the word "amend" does not
support the contention that an amendment must take an improvement, see Oxford
English Dictionary where the word "amend" is defined thus : "4.
to make professed improvements (in a measure before Parliament);
formally to alter 'in detail, though
practically it may be to alter its principle so as to thwart it." The 1st,
4th, 16th and. 17th Amendment Acts made changes in Part III of the
Constitution. All the changes are authorized by art.
368.
It is argued that under the amending power,
the basic features .,of the Constitution cannot be amended. Counsel said that
they could not give an exhaustive catalogue of the basic features, but
sovereignty, the republican form of government the federal structure and the
fundamental rights were some of the features. The Seventeenth Amendment has not
derogated from the sovereignty, ,the republican form of government and the
federal structure, and 'the question whether they can be touched by amendment
does not arise for decision. For the purposes of these cases, it is sufficient
to saythat the fundamental rights are within the reach of the amending power.
It is said that in the course of the last 16
years there have been numerous amendments in our Constitution whereas there
have been very few amendments of the American Constitution during 'the last 175
years. Our condition is not comparable with the American. The dynamics of the
social revolution in our country may require more rapid changes. Moreover every
part of our Constitution is more easily amendable than the American. Alan
Gledhill in his book "The Republic of India", 1951 Edition, pp. 74
& 75 , said:
"The Indian Founding, Fathers were less
determined than were their American predecessors to impose rigidity on their
Constitution..................... The Indian Constitution assigns different
degrees of rigidity to its different parts, but any part of it can be more easily
amended than the American Constitution." It is said that the Parliament is
abusing its power of amendment by making too many frequent changes. If the
Parliament 'has the powerto make the amendments, the choice of makingany
particular amendment must be left to it. Questions of policy cannot be debated
in ' this Court.
The possibility of, abuse of a power is not
the test of its existence. In Webb v. Outrim(1) lord (1) [1907] A.C. 81.
917 Hobhouse said, "If they find that on
the due construction of the Act a legislative power falls within s. 92, it
would be quite wrong of them to deny its existence because by some possibility
it may be abused, or limit the range which otherwise would be open to the
Dominion Parliament". With reference to the doctrine of implied
prohibition against the exercise of power ascertained in accordance with
ordinary rules of construction, Knox C.J., in the Amalgamated Society of
Engineers v. The Adelaide Steams Company Limited and others(1) said, "It
means the necessity of protection against the aggression of some outside and
possibly hostile body. :It is based on distrust, lest powers, if once conceded
to the least degree, might be abused to the point of destruction. But possible
abuse of powers is no reason in British law for Emiting the natural force of
the language creating them The historical background in which the Constitution
was framed shows that the ideas embodied in Part III were not intended to be
immutable. The Constituent Assembly was corn of representatives of the
provinces elected by,the members of the lower houses of the provincial
legislatures and representatives of the Indian States elected by electoral
colleges constituted by the rules. The draft Constitution was released on
February 26, 1948While the Constitution was on the anvil it was envisaged the,
future Parliaments would be elected on the basis of adult suffrage. Such a
provision was later incorporated in art. 326 of the Constitution. In a special
article written on August 15, 1948, Sir B., N. Rau remarked:
"It seems rather illogical that a
constitution should be settled by a simple majority by an assembly elected
indirectly on a very limited franchise and that it should not be capable of
being amended in the same way by a Parliament elected-and perhaps for the most
Part elected directly by adult suffrage", (see B. N. Rau' India's
Constitution in the making, 2nd Edition p. 394).
The conditions in India were rapidly changing
and the country was in a state of flux politically and economically.
Sir B. N. Rau therefore recommended that the
Parliament should be empowered to amend the Constitution by its ordinary law
making process for at least the first five years. Earlier, para 8 of the
Suggestions of the Indian National Congress of May 12, 1946 and para 15 of the
Proposal of the Cabinet Mission of May 16, 1946 had recommended similar powers
of revision by the Parliament during the initial years or at stated intervals.
The Constituent Assembly did notaccept these recommendations. On September 17,
1949 an amendment (No. 304) moved by Dr.
Deshmukh providing (1) 28 C.L.R. 129,151.
Cf/67-13 918 for amendment of the
Constitution at any time by a clear majority in each house of Parliament was
negatived. The Assembly was conscious that future Parliaments, elected on the
basis of adult suffrage would be more representative, but they took the view
that art. 368 provided a sufficiently flexible machinery for amending all
part-, of the Constitution. The Assembly never entertain the proposal that any
part of the Constitution including Part III should be beyond the reach of the,
amending power. As a matter of fact, Dr. Deshmukh proposed an amendment (No.
212) habiting any amendment of the rights with respect to property or otherwise
but on September 17, 1949 he withdrew this proposal (we Constituent Assembly
Debates Vol. IV pp. 1 642-43).
The best exposition of the Constitution is
that which it has received from contemporaneous judicial decisions and
enactments. We find a rare unanimity of view among Judges and legislators from
the very commencement of the Constitution that the fundamental rights are
within the reach of the amending power. No one in the Parliament doubted this
proposition when the Constitution First Amendment Act of 1951 was passed. It is
remarkable that most of the members of this Parliament were also. members of
the Constituent Assembly. In, S. Krishnan and Others v. The state of Madras(1),
a case decided on May 7, 1951 Bose, J.
said:
"My concept of a fundamental right is
something which Parliament cannot touch save by an amendment of the
Constitution". , In Sri Sankari Prasad Singh Deo's case(2), decided on
October 5, 1951, this Court expressly decided thatfundamental rights could be
abridged by a constitutional amendment. This view was acted upon in all the
subsequent decisions and was reaffirmed in Sajjan Singh's case(3). Two learned
Judges then expressed some doubt but even they agreed with the rest of the
Court in upholding the validity of the amendments.
A static system of. laws is the worst tyranny
that any constitution can impose upon a country.. An unamendable constitution
means that all. reform and progress are at a standstill. If Parliament cannot
amend Part III of the Constitution even by recourse to art. 368, no other power
can do so. There is no, provision in the Constitution for calling a convention
for its revision or for submission of any proposal for amendment to the
referendum. Even if power to call a convention or to submit a proposal. to the
refere be taken by amendment of art. 368, Part III. would sip remain
unamendable on the assumption that a constitutional amendment is a law. Not
even the unanimous vote of the 500 (1) [1951] S.C.R. 621, 652.
(2) [1952] S. C. R, 89.
(3) [1965] 1 S. C. R. 933.
919 million citizens or their representatives,
at a special convocation could amend Part III. The deadlock could be resolved
by revolution only. Such a consequence was not intended by the framers of the
Constitution. The Constitution is meant to endure.
It has been suggested that the Parliament may
provide for another Constituent Assembly by amending the Constitution and that
Assembly can amend Part III and take away or abridge "the fundamental
rights. Now if this proposition is correct, a suitable amendment of the
Constitution may provide that the Parliament will be the Constituent Assembly
and there upon the Parliament may amend Part III. If so, I do not see why under
the Constitution as it stands now, the Parliament cannot be regarded as a
recreation of the Constituent Assembly. for the special purpose of making a
constitutional amendments under art. 368, and why the amending power cannot be
regarded a a constituent power as was held in Sri Sankari Prasad-Singh Deo's
(1) case.
The contention that the constitutional
amendments of Part III had the effect (I changing articles 226 and 245 and
could not be passed without complying with the proviso to art. 368 is not
tenable; A constitutional amendment which does not profess to amendart. 226
directly or by inserting or striking words therein cannot be regarded as
seeking to make, any change in it and thus falling within the constitutional
inhibition of the proviso. Art. 226 gives power to the High Court throughout
the territories in relation to which it exercises jurisdiction to issue to any
person or authority within those territories directions, orders and Writs for
the enforcement of any of the rights conferred by Part III and for any purposeThe
Seventeenth Amendment made no direct change in art. 226. It made changes in
Part In and abridged or took away some of the rights conferred by that Part. As
a result of the changes, some of those rights no longer exist and as the High
Court cannot issue writs for the enforcement of those rights its power under
art. 226 is affected incidentally. But an alteration in the area of its
territories or in the number of persons or authorities within those territories
or in the number of enforceable rights under Part III or other rights
incidentally affecting the Power of the High Court under art. 226 cannot be
regarded as an' amendment of that article.
Art. 245 empowers the Parliament and the
Legislatures-of, the States to make laws subject to the provisions of the
Constitution. This power to make laws is subject to the limitations imposed by
Part M. The abridgement of the rights conferred by Part III by the Seventeenth
Amendment necessarily enlarged the scope of the legislate power, and thus
affected art. 245 indirectly. But the Seventeenth amendment made no direct
change in art. 145 and did not amend it.
(1) [1952] S.C.R. 89.
920 Art 3 1B retrospectively validated the
Acts mentioned in the Ninth Schedule notwithstanding any judgment decree or
order of any court though they take away or abridge the rights conferred by
Part Ill. It is said that the Acts are still-bom and cannot be validated. But
by force of Art. 31B the Acts are deemed never to have become void and must be
regarded as valid from their inception. The power to amend the Constitution
carries with it the power to make a retrospective amendment. It is Said that
art. 3 1B amends art. 141 as it alters the law declared by this Court on the
validity of the Acts. This argument is baseless. As the Constitution is amended
retrospectively, the basis upon which the judgments of this Court were
pronounced no longer exists, and the law declared by this Court can have no
application. It is said that art. 3 1B is a law with respect to land and other
matters within the competence of the State Legislature, and the Parliament has
no power to enact such a law. The argument is based on a misconception.
The Parliament has not passed any of the Acts
mentioned in the Ninth Schedule. Art. 3 IB removed the constitutional bar on
the making of the Acts. Only the Parliament could remove the bar by the
Constitution amendment. It has done so by art. 3 1 B. The Parliament could
amend each article in Part III separately and provide that the Acts would be
protected from attack under each article. Instead of amending each article
separately, the Parliament has by art. 3 1 B made a comprehensive amendment of
all the articles by providing that the Acts shall not be deemed to be void on
the ground that they are inconsistent with any of them. The Acts as they stood
on the date of the Constitution Amendments are validated. By the last part of
Art. 31B the competent legislatures will continue to the power to repeal or
amend the Acts. The subsequent repeals and amendments are not validated. If in
future the competent legislature passes a repealing or amending Act which is
inconsistent with Part III it will be void.
I have, therefore, coma to the conclusion
that the First, Fourth, Sixteenth and Seventeenth Amendments are constitutional
and am not void. If so, it is common ground that these petitions must be For
the last 16 years the validity of constitutional amendments of fundamental
rights have been recognized by the people and all the organs of the government
'including the legislature, the judiciary and the executive.
Revolutionary, social and economic changes
have taken place on the strength of the First, Fourth and Seventeenth
Amendments. Even if two views were possible on the question of, the validity of
the amendments, we should not now reverse our previous decisions and pronounce
them to be invalid. Having heard lengthy arguments on the question I have 921
come to the conclusion that the validity of the constitutional amendments was
rightly upheld in Sri Sankari Prasad Singh Deo's(1) and Sajjan Singh's(2) cases
and I find no reason for over-ruling them.
The First, Fourth and Seventeenth amendment
Acts are subjected to bitter attacks because they strike it the entrenched
property rights. But the abolition of the zemindari was a necessary reform. It
is the First Constitution Amendment Act that made this reform possible.
No legal argument can restore the outmoded
feudal zemindari system. What has been done cannot be undone. The battle for
the past is lost. The legal argument necessarily shifts. The proposition now is
that the Constitution Amendment Acts must be recognized to be valid in the past
but they must be struck down for the future. The argument leans on the ready
made American doctrine of prospective overruling.
Now the First, Fourth, Sixteenth and
Seventeenth Amendment Acts take away and abridge the rights conferred by Part M.
If they are laws they are necessarily
rendered void by art.
13(2). If they are void, they do not legally
exist from their very inception. They cannot be valid from 1951 to 1967 and
invalid thereafter. To say that they were valid in the past and will be invalid
in the future is to amend the Constitution. Such a naked power of amendment of
the Constitution is not given to the Judges. The argument for the petitioners
suffers from a double fallacy, the first that the Parliament has no power to
amend Part III so as to abridge or take away the entrenched property rights,
and the second that the Judges have the power to make such an amendment.
I may add that if the First and the Fourth
amendments are valid, the Seventeenth must necessarily be valid. It is not
possible to say that the First and Fourth amendments though originally invalid
have now been validated by acquiescence.
If they infringed art. 13(2),t they were void
from their inception. Referring to the 19th amendment of the U.S.
Constitution, Brandeis, J. said in Leser v.
Garnett(3) "This Amendment is in character and phraseology precisely
similar to the 15th.
For each the same method of adoption was
pursued. One cannot be valid and the other invalid. That the 15th is valid,
although rejected by six states, including Maryland, has been recognized and
acted on for half a century.......... The suggestion that the 15th was
incorporated in the Constitution, (1) [1952] S.C.R. 89. (2) [1965] 1 S.C.R.
933.
(3) 258 US 130 : 66 L.Ed.. 505, 51 1.
922 not in accordance with law, but
practically as a war measure, which has been validated by acquiescence, cannot
be entertained." Moreover the Seventeenth amendment has been acted upon
and its validity has been upheld by this Court in Sajjan Singh's case. If the First
and the Fourth Amendments are validated by acquiescence, the Seventeenth is
equally validated.
Before concluding this judgment I must refer
to some of the speeches made by the members of the Constituent Assembly in the
course of debates on the draft Constitution. These speeches cannot be used as
aids for interpreting the Constitution. See State of Travancore-Cochin and
others v.
The Bombay Co. Ltd.('-). Accordingly, I do
not rely on them as aids to construction. But I propose to refer to them, as
Shri A K. Sen relied heavily on the speeches of Dr. B. R.
Ambedkar. According to him, the speeches of
Dr. Ambedkar show that he did not regard the fundamental rights as amendable.
This contention is not supported by the speeches. Sri Sen relied on the following
passage in the speech of Dr. Ambedkar on September 17, 1949 "We divide the
articles of the Constitution under three categories. The first category is the
one which consists of articles which can be, amended by Parliament by a bare
majority.
The second set of articles are articles which
require two-thirds majority. If the future Parliament wishes to amend any
particular article .which is not mentioned in Part III orart. 304, all that is
necessary for them is to have two-thirds majority. They can amend it.
Mr. President : Of Members present.
Yes. Now, we have no doubt put articles in a
third .category where for the purposes of amendment the .mechanism is somewhat
different or double. It requires two thirds majority plus ratification by the,
States."(2) I understand this passage to mean that according to Dr. Ambedkar
an amendment of the articles mentioned in Part. III and 368 requires two-thirds
majority plus ratification by the States He seems to have assumed (as reported)
that the provisions of Part III fall within the. proviso to art. 368.
But he never said that part III was s not
amendale. He maintained consistently that all the articles of the Constitution
are amendable under art. 368 On November 4, 1948, be. said :
"The second means adopted to avoid
rigidity and legalism is the provision for facility with which the (1) (1952]
S.C.R. 1112.
(2) Constituent Assembly Debat Vol. IX p.
1661.
923 Constitution could be amended. The
provisions of the Constitution relating to the amendment of the Constitution
divide the Articles of the Constitution into two groups. In the one group are
placed Articles relating to (a) the distribution of legislative powers between
the Centre and the States, (b) the representation of the States in Parliament,
and (c) the powers of I the Courts. All other Articles are placed in another
group. Articles placed in the second group cover a very large part of the
Constitution and can be amended by Parliament by a double majority, namely, a
majority of not less than two-thirds of the members of each House present and
voting and by a majority of the total membership of each House. The amendment
of these Articles does not require ratification by the States. It is only in
those Articles which are placed in group one that an additional safeguard of
ratification by the States is introduced. One can therefore safely sky that the
Indian Federation will not suffer from the faults of rigidity or legalism. Its
distinguishing feature is that it is a flexible Federation.
The provisions relating to amendment of the
Constitution have come in for a virulent attack at the hands of the critics of
the Draft Constitution. it is said that the provisions contained in the Draft
make amendment difficult. It is proposed that the Constitution should be amendable
by a simple majority at least for some. years. The argument is subtle and
ingenious. It is said that this Constituent Assembly is not elected on adult
suffrage while the future Parliament will be elected on adult suffrage and yet
the former has been given the right to pass the Constitution by a simple
majority while 'the latter has been denied the same right. It is paraded as one
of the absurdities of the Draft Constitution. I must repudiate the charge
because it is without foundation. To know how simple are the provisions of the
Draft Constitution in respect of amending the Constitution one has only to
study the provisions for amendment contained in the American and Australian
Constitutions.
'Compared to them those contained in the
Draft Constitution will be found to be the simplest.
'The Draft Constitution has eliminated theelaborate
and difficult procedures such as a decisionby a convention or are ferenduni.
The Powers of amendments left with the
Legislatures Central and Provincial. It is only, for amendment-, or specific
matters-and they are only few, that the ratification of the State Legislatures
is required.
924 All other Articles of the Constitution
are left to be amended by Parliament. The only limitation is that it shall be
done by a majority, of not less than two-thirds of the members of each House
present and voting and a majority of the total membership of each House. It is
difficult to conceive a simpler method of amending the Constitution."(,')
On December 9, 1948 , Dr. Ambedkar said with reference to art. 32:
"The Constitution has invested the
Supreme Court with these rights and these writs could not be taken away unless
and until the Constitution itself is amended by means left open to the
legislature."(2) On November25, 1949, Dr. Ambedkar strongly refuted the
suggestion that fundamental rights should' be absolute and unalterable. He
said:
"The condemnation of the Constitution
largely comes from-two quarters, the Communist Party and the Socialist
Party.......... The second thing that the Socialists want is that the
Fundamental Rights mentioned in the Constitution must be absolute and without
any limitations so that if their Party comes into power, they would have the
unfettered freedom not merely to criticize, but also to overthrow the
State............ Jefferson, the great American statesman who played so great a
part in the making of the American Constitution, has expressed some very
weighty views which makers of Constitution can never afford to ignore. In one
place, he has said:'We may consider each generation as a distinct nation, with
a right, by the will of the majority, to bind themselves, but none to bind the
succeeding generation, more than the inhabitants of another country. In another
place, he has said: 'The idea that institutions established for the use of the
nation cannot be touched or modified, even to make them answer their end,
because of rights gratuitously supposed in those employed to manage the min the
trust for the public, may perhaps be a Salutary provision against the abuses of
a monarch, but is most absurd against the nation itself. Yet our lawyers and
priests generally inculcate this doctrine, and suppose that preceding
generations held the earth more freely than we do; had a right to impose laws
on us, unalterable by ourselves, and (1) Constituent Assembly Debates Vol. 7,
pp.
35-6, 43-4.
(2) Constituent Assembly Debates Vol. 7, 953.
925 that we, in the like manner, can make
laws and impose burdens on future generations, which they will have no right to
alter; in fine, that the earth belongs to the dead and not the living. I admit
that what Jefferson has said is not merely true, but is absolutely true.
There can be no question about it. Had the
Constituent Assembly departed from this principle laid down by Jefferson it
would certainly be liable to blame, even to condemnation. But I ask, has it?
Quite the contrary. One has only to examine the provision relating to the
amendment of the Constitution. The Assembly has not only refrained from putting
a seal of finality and infallibility upon this Constitution by denying to the
people the right to amend the Constitution as in Canada or by making the
amendment of the Constitution subject to the fulfilment of extraordinary terms
and conditions as in America of Australia but has provided a most facile
procedure for amending the Constitution. I challenge any of the critics of the
Constitution to prove that any Constituent Assembly anywhere in the world has,
in the circumstances in which this country finds itself, provided such a facile
procedure for the amendment of the Constitution. If those who are dissatisfied
with the Constitution have only to obtain a 2/3 majority and if they cannot
obtain even a twothirds majority in the parliament elected on adult franchise
in their favour, their dissatisfaction with the Constitution cannot be deemed
to be shared by the general public.'(1) On November 11, 1948, Pandit Jawahar
Lal Nehru said:
"And remember this, that while we want
this Constitution to be as solid and as permanent a structure as we can make
it, nevertheless there is no permanence in Constitutions.
There should be a certain flexibility. If you
make anything rigid and permanent, you stop a Nation's growth, the growth of
living vital organic people. Therefore it has to be flexible."(2) The
views of Jefferson echoed by Ambedkar and Nehru were more powerful expressed by
Thomas Paine in 1791 "There never did, there never will, and there never
can, exist a parliament, or any description of men, or any generation of men,
in any country, possessed of the (1) Constituent Assembly Debates Vol. I 1, pp.
975-6.
(2) Constituent Assembly Debates Vol. 7, p.
322.
926 right or the power of binding and
controuling posterity to the end of time', or of commanding for ever how the
world. shall be governed, or who shall govern it-, and therefore all such
clauses, acts or declarations by which the makers of them attempt to do what
they have neither the right nor the power to do, nor take power to execute, are
in themselves null and void.
Every age and generation must be as free to
act for itself in all cases as the ages and generations which preceded it. The
vanity and presumption of governing beyond the grave is the most ridiculous and
insolent of all tyrannies. Man has no property in man;
neither has any generation a property in the
generations which are to follow. The parliament of the people of 1688 or of any
other period, had no more right to dispose of the people of the present day, or
to bind or to controul them in any shape whatever, than the parliament or the
people of the present day have to dispose of, bind or controul those who are to
live a hundred or a thousand years hence. Every Generation is, and must be,
competent to all the purposes which its occasions require. It is the living,
and not the dead, that are to be accommodated. When man ceases to be, his power
and his wants cease with him; and having no longer any participation in the
concerns of this World, he has no longer any authority in directing who shall be
its governors, or how its government shall be organized, or how
administered." (See 'Rights of Man' by Thomas Paine, unabridged edition by
H. B. Bonner, pp.
3 & 4).
For the reasons given above, I agree with
Wanchoo, J. that the writ petitions must be dismissed.
In the result, the writ petitions are
dismissed without costs.
Ramaswami, J. I have perused the judgment of
my learned Brother Wanchoo, J. and I agree with his conclusion that the
Constitution (Seventeenth Amendment) Act, 1964 is legally valid, but in view of
the importance.of the constitutional issues raised in this case I would prefer
to state, my own reasons in a separate judgment.
In these petitions which have been filed
under Art. 32 of the Constitution, a common question arises for determination,
viz.,. whether the Constitution (Seventeenth Amendment) Act, 1964 which amends
Art. 31 A and 3 1 B of the Constitution is ultra viresand unconstitutional, .
927 The petitioners are affected either by
the Punjab Security of Land Tenures Act, 1954. (Act X of 1953) or by the Mysore
Land Reforms Act (Act 10 of 1962) as amended by Act 1 1965 which were added to
the 9th Schedule of the Constitution by the impugned Act and, their contention
is that the impugned Act being unconstitutional and invalid , the validity of
the two Acts by which they are affected cannot be saved.
The impugned Act consists of three sections.
The first section. gives its short title. Section 2 (i) adds a proviso to Cl..
( 1 ) of Art.. 3 I-A after the existing proviso. This proviso reads, thus:
"Provided further that where any law
makes any provision for the acquisition by the State of any estate and where
any land comprised therein is held by a person under his personal cultivation,
it shall not be lawful for the State to acquire any portion of such land as is
within the ceiling limit applicable to him under any law for the time being in
force or any building or structure standing thereon or appurtenant thereto,
unless the law relating to the acquisition of such land, building or structure,
provides for payment of compensation at a rate which shall not be less than the
market value thereof." Section 2(ii) substitutes the following subclause
for sub-cl. (a) of cl. (2) of Art. 31-A "(a) the expression 'estate'
shall, in relation to any local area, have the same meaning as that expression
or its local equivalent-has in the existing law relating force in that area and
all to land tenures in also include(i) any jagir, inam or muafi or other
similar grant and in the States-of Madras and Kerala, any ianmam right;
(ii) any land held under ryotwari settlement;
(iii) any land held or let for purposes of
agriculture or for purposes ancillary there to, including wast land, forest
land, land for posture or ones of buildings and other structures occupied by
cultivators of land, agricultural labourers and village artisans;" Section
3 amends the 9th Schedule by adding 44 entries to it.
In dealing with the question about the
validity of the impugned Act, it is necessary to consider the scope and effect
of the provisions contained in-Art. 368 of the Constitution, because the main
controversy in the present applications turns upon:the928 decision of the
question as to what is the construction of that Article. Article 368 reads as
follows:
"An amendment of this Constitution may
be initiated only by the introduction of a Bill for the-purpose in either House
of Parliament, and when the Bill is passed in each House by a majority of the
total membership of that House and by a majority of not less than two-thirds of
the members of that House present and voting, it shall be presented to the
President for his assent and upon such assent being given to the Bill, the
Constitution shall stand amended in accordance with the terms of the Bill .
Provided that if such amendment seeks to make
any change (a) Article 5, article 55, article, 73, article 162 or article 241,
or (b) Chapter IV of Part V, Chapter V of Part VI, or Chapter I of Part XI, or
(c) any of the Lists in the Seventh Schedule, or (d) the representation of
States in Parliament, or (e) the provisions of this article, the amendment
shall also require to be ratified by the Legislatures of not less than one-half
of the States by resolutions to that effect passed by those. Legislatures
before the Bill making provision for such amendment is presented to the
President for assent." It is necessary at this stage to set out briefly
the history of Arts. ..31-A and 31-B. These Articles were added to the
Constitution with retrospective effect by s. 4 of the Constitution (First
Amendment) Act, 1951. Soon after the promulgation of the Constitution, the
political party in power, commanding as it did a majority of votes in the
several State legislatures as well as in Parliament, carried out radical
measures of agrarian reform in Bihar, may be referred to as Zamindari Abolition
Acts. Certain zamindars, feeling themselves aggrieved, attacked the validity of
those Acts in courts of law on the ground that they contravened the
'fundamental rights conferred on them by Part III of the Constitution. The High
Court of Patna held that the Act passed iii Bihar was unconstitutional while
the High Courts of Allahabad and Nagpur upheld the validity of the
corresponding legislation in Uttar Pradesh and Madhya Pradesh respectively (See
Kameshwar Uttar Pradesh and Madhya Pradesh by enacting legislation which 929 v.
State of Bihar(1) and Surya Pal v. U.P. Government(1).
The parties aggrieved by these respective
decisions had filed appeals by special leave before this Court.At the same time
petitions had also been preferred before this Court under Art. 32 by certain
other Zamindars, seeking the determination of the same issues It was atstage
that the Union Government, with a view to put an endall this litigation and to
remedy what they considered to be certain defects brought to light in the work
of the Constitution, brought forward a bill to amend the Constitution, which,.
after undergoing amendments in various
particulars, was passed by the require majority as the Constitution (First Amendment)
Act, 1951 by which Arts. 31-A and 31-B were added to the Constitution. That was
the first step taken by Parliament to assist the process of legislation to
bring about agrarian reform, by introducing Articles 31-A and 31B. The second
step in the same direction was taken by Parliament in 1955 by amending Art.
31-A by the Constitution (Fourth Amendment) Act, 1955.. The object of this
amendment was to widen the scope of agrarian reform and to confer on the
legislative measures adopted in that behalf immunity from a possible attack
that they contravened' the fundamental rights of citizens. In other words, the
amendment Protected the legislative measures in respect of certain other items
of agrarian and social welfare legislation, which affected the proprietary
rights of certain citizens. At the time when the first amendment was made, Art.
31-B expressly provided that none, of the, Acts and Regulations specified in
the 9th Schedule, nor any of the provisions thereof, shall be deemed to be void
or ever to have become void on the ground that they were inconsistent with or
took: away or abridged any of the rights conferred by Part III, and it added
that notwithstanding any judgment, decree or order of any Court or tribunal to
the contrary, each of the said Acts and Regulations shall subject to the power
of any competent legislature to repeal or amend, continue in force. At this
time, 19 Acts were listed in Schedule 9, and they were thus effectively
validated. One more Act was added to this list by the Amendment Act of 1955, so
that as a result of the second amendment, the Schedule contained 20 Acts which
were validated.
It appears that notwithstanding these
amendments, certain other legislative measures adopted by different States for
the purpose of giving effect to the agrarian policy of the party in power, were
effectively challenged. For instance, the Karimbil Kunhikoman v. State of
Kerala(3), the validity of the Kerala Agrarian Relations Act (IV of 1961) was
challenged by writ petitions filed under Art. 32, and as a result of the
majority decision of this Court, the whole Act was struck down. The decision of
this (1) A-I-R. 1951 Pat. 91 (2) A.I.R. 1951 All. 674.
(3)[1962] Supp. 1 S.CR. 829..
930 Court was pronounced on December 5, 1961.
In A. P. Krishnaswami Naidu v. The State of Madras(1) the constitutionality of
the Madras Land Reforms (Fixation of Ceiling on Land) Act (146. 58 of 1961) was
the subject matter of debate, and by the decision of this Court pronounced, on
March 9, 1964, it was declared that the whole Act was invalid. It appears that
the Rajas than Tenancy Act III of 1955 and the Maharashtra Agricultural Lands
(Ceiling and Holdings) Act 27 of 1961 had been similarly declared invalid, and
in consequence, Parliament thought it necessary to make a further amendment in
Art: 31-B so as to gave the validity of these Acts which had been struck down
and of other similar Acts which were likely to be challenged. With that object
in view, the impugned Act has enacted S. 3 by which 44 Acts have been added to
Schedule 9. It is therefore clear that the object of the First, Fourth and the
Seventeenth Amendments of the Constitution was to help the State Legislatures
to give effect to measures of agrarian reform in a broad and comprehensive
sense in the interests of a very large section of Indian ,citizens whose social
and economic welfare closely depends on the persuit of progressive agrarian
policy.
The first question presented for
determination in this case is whether the impugned Act, in so far as it purports
to take away or abridge any of the fundamental rights conferred by Part III .or
the Constitution,falls within the prohibition of Art. 13 (2) which provides
that "the State, 'shall, not make any law which takes away or abridges the
rights conferred by this Part and any law made in contravention of this clause
shall to the extent of the Contravention, be void". In other words, the
argument, of the petitioners was that the law to which Art, 13(2) applies,
would include a law passed by Parliament by virtue of its constituent power to
amend the Constitution, and so, its validity will have. to be tested by Art.
13(2) itself.
It was contended that the State"
includes Parliament within Art. 12 and "law" must include, a
constitutional amendment.
It was said that it was the deliberate
intention of the framers of the Constitution, who realised the sanctity of the
fundamental rights conferred by Part III, to make them immune from interference
not only by ordinary laws passed by the legislatures in the country but also
from constitutional amendments. In my opinion, there is no substance in this
argument.Although "law" must ordinarily include constitutional law,
there is 'a juristic distinction between ordinary law made in exercise of
legislative power and constitutional law which is Made in exercise of
constituent power. In a written federal form of Constitution there is a clear
and well-known distinction between the law of the Constitution and ordinary law
made by the legislature on the basis of separation of powers and (1)[1964]7
S.C.R.82.
931 pursuant to the power of law-making
conferred by the Constitution (See Dicey on 'Law of the Constitution, Tenth:
Edn.
p. 110, Jennings, 'Law and the Constitution'
pp. 62-64, and 'American Jurisprudence', 2nd Edn. Vol. 16, p. 181). In such a
written Constitution, the amendment of the Constitution is .a substantive,
constituent act which is made in the exercise, of the sovereign power which
created the Constitution and which is effected by a special means, namely, by a
predesigned fundamental procedure unconnected with ordinary legislation. The
amending power under Art.
368 is hence sui generis and cannot be,
compared to the lawmaking power of Parliament pursuant to Art. 246 read with
List I and 111. It follows that the expresSion "law" in Art. 13(2) of
the Constitution cannot be construed as including an amendment of the
Constitution which is by Parliament in exercise of, its sovereign constituent
power, but must mean law made by Parliament in its legislative capacity :pursuant
to the powers of law-making given by the Constitution itself under Art. 246
read with Lists I and In of the 7th Schedule. It is also clear, on the same
line of reasoning, that 'law' in Art. 13(2) cannot be construed so as to
include 'law' made by Parliament under Arts. 4, 169, 392, 5th Schedule Part D
and 6th Schedule para 2 1. The amending power of Parliament exercised under
these Articles stands on the same as the constitutional amendment made under
Art. U8 so far as Art. 13(2) is concerned and does not fall within the
definition of law within the meaning of this last article.
It is necessary to add that the definition of
'law' in Art.
13(3) does not include in terms a
constitutional amendments though it includes "any Ordinance,, order,
bye-law, rule, regulation, notification, custom or usage ". It should be
noticed that The language. of Art. 3 6 8 is perfectly general and empowers
Parliament to amend the Constitution without any exception Whatsoever. H I ad
it been intended by the Constitution-makers that the fundamental rights
guaranteed under Part III should be completely outside the scope of Art. 368,
it is reasonable to assume that they would have made an express provision to
that effect. It was stressed by the petitioners during the course 'of the,
argument that Part III is headed as 'Fundamental Rights" and that Art. 32
"guarantee's' the right to move the Supreme Court by appropriate
proceedings for enforcement of rights conferred by Part M. But the expression
"fundamental" in the phrase "Fundamental Rights" means that
such rights are fundamental vis-a-vis the laws of the legislatures and the acts
of the executive authorities mentioned in Art. 12. It cannot be suggested, that
the expression "fundamental" lifts the fundamental rights above the Constitution
itself.
Similarly, the expression "guaranteed'
in Art. 32(1) and 32(4) means that the right to move the Supreme Court for
enforcement of fundamental rights without 932 exhausting the, normal channels
through the High Courts or the lower courts is guaranteed. This expression also
does not place the fundamental rights above the Constitution.
I proceed to consider the next question
arising in this case, the scope of the amending power under Art. 368 of the
Constitution. It is contended on behalf of the petitioners that Art. 368 merely
lays down the procedure for amendment and does not vest the amending power as
such in any agency constituted under that article. I am unable to accept this
argument as correct Part XX of the Constitution which contains only Art. 368 is
described as a Part dealing with the Amendment of the Constitution and Art. 368
which prescribes the procedure for amendment of the Constitution, begins by
saying that an amendment of this Constitution may be initiated in the manner therein
indicated. In MY Opinion, the expression "amendment of the
Constitution" in Art. 368 plainly and unambiguously means amendment of all
the provisions of the Constitution. It is unreasonable to suggest that what
Art. 368 provides is only the mechanics of the procedure to be followed in
amending the Constitution without indicating which provisions of the
Constitution can be amended and which cannot. Such a restrictive construction
of the substantive part of Art. 368 would be clearly untenable. The significant
fact , that a separate Part has been devoted in the Constitution for
"amendment of the Constitution and there is only one Article in that Part
shows that both the power to amend and the procedure to amend are enacted in
Art. 368. Again, the words "the Constitution shall stand amended in
accordance with the terms of the Bill" in Art. 368 clearly contemplate and
provide for the power to amend after the requisite procedure has been followed.
Besides, the words used in the proviso unambiguously indicate that the
substantive part of the article applied to all the provisions of the
Constitution.
It is on that basic assumption that the
proviso prescribes a specific procedure in respect of the amendment of ,the
articles mentioned in cls. (a) to (e) thereof. Therefore it must be held that
when Art. 368 confers on Parliament the right to amend the Constitution the
power in question can be exercised over all the provisions of the Constitution.
How the power should be exercised, has to be determined by reference to the
question as to whether the proposed amendment falls under the substantive part
of Art. 368, or whether it attracts the procedure contained in the proviso.
It was suggested for the petitioners that the
power of amendment is to be found in Arts. 246 and 248 of the constitution read
with item 97 of List I of the 7th Schedule. I do not think that it is possible
to accept this argument. Article 246 stats that 933 Parliament has exclusive
power to make laws with respect to matters enumerated in List I in the Seventh
Schedule, and Art. 248, similarly, confers power on Parliament to make any law
with respect to any matter not enumerated in the Concurrent List or State List.
But the power of law-making in Arts. 246 and 248 is "subject to the
provisions of this Constitution". It is apparent that the power of
constitutional amendment cannot fall within these Articles, because it is
illogical and a contradiction in terms to say that the amending power can be
exercised and at the same time it is "subject to the provisions of, the
Constitution".
It was then submitted on behalf of the
petitioners that the amending power under Art. 368 is subject to the doctrine
of implied limitations. In other words, it was contended that even if Art. 368
confers the power of. amendment, it was not a general but restricted power
confined only to the amendable provisions of the Constitution, the amendability
of such provision being determined by the nature and character of the
respective provision. It was argued, for instance, that the amending power
cannot be used to abolish the compact of the Union or to destroy the democratic
character of the Constitution teeing individual and minority rights. It was
said that the Constitution was a permanent compact of the States, that the
federal character of the States was individual, and that the existence of any.
of the States as part of the federal Compact Cannot4be put an end to by the
power of amendment. It was also said that the chapter of fundamental rights of
the Constitution cannot be the subject-matter of any amendment under Art. 368.
It was contended that the preamble to the Constitution declaring that India was
a sovereign democratic republic was beyond the scope of the amending Power. it,
was suggested that other basic, features of the Constitution were the Articles
relating to. distribution of legislative powers, the Parliamentary form of
Government and the establishment of Supreme Court and the High, Courts in the
various States. .
I am unable to accept this argument as
correct. If the Constitution-makers considered that there were certain basic
features of the Constitution which were permanent it. is must unlikely that
they should not have expressly said in Art 368 that these basic features were.
not amendable. On the contrary, the Constitution-makers have expressly
provided. that Art. 368 itself should be amendable by the process indicated in
the proviso to that Article. This circumstance is significant and suggests.
that all the articles of the Constitution are amendable either under the
proviso to Art. 368 or under the main part of that Article. In MY opinion,
there is no room for an. implication in the construction of Art. 368. So far as
the federal character of the Constitution is concerned, it was held by this
Court in State of West Bengal v. Union of Cl/67-14 934 India(1) that the
federal structure is not an essential pan of our Constitution and there is no
compact between the States and them is no dual citizenship in India. It was
pointed out in that case that there was no constitutional guarantee against the
alteration of boundaries of the States. By An. 3 the Parliament is by law
authorised to form a new State by redistribution of the territory of a.
State or by uniting two or more States or
parts of States or by uniting any territory to a part of any State, to increase
the area of any State, to diminish the area of any State to alter the
boundaries of any State, and to alter the name of any State. In In Re The
Berubari Union and Exchange of Enclaves (2) it was argued that the
Indo-Pakistan agreement with regard to Berubari could not be implemented even
by legislation under Art. 368 because of the limitation imposed by the preamble
to the Constitution and that such an agreement could not be implemented by a
referendum. The argument was rejected by this Court and it was held that the
preamble could not, 'in i any way, limit the power of Parliament to cede parts
of the national territory. On behalf of the petitioners the argument was s that
the chapter on fundamental rights was the basic feature, of the Constitution
and cannot be the subject of the amending power under Art 368. It was argued
that the freedoms of democratic life are secured by the chapter on fundamental
rig its and dignity of the individual cannot be preserved if any of the
fundamental rights is altered or diminished. It is not possible to accept this
argument as correct. The concepts of liberty and equality are changing and
dynamic and hence the notion of permanency or immutability cannot be attached
to any of the fundamental rights. The Directive Principles of Part IV are as
fundamental as the constitutional rights embodied in Part III and Art. 37
imposes a constitutional duty upon the States to apply these principles in
making laws. Reference should in particular be made to Art. 39(b) which enjoins
upon the State to direct its policy towards securing that the ownership and
control of the material resources of the community are so distributed as best
to subserve the common good. Art. 3 8 imposes a duty upon, the State to promote
the welfare of the people by securing and protecting as effectively as it may,
a social order in which justice, social, economic and political, shall inform
all the institutions of the national life. I have already said that the
language of Art. 368 is clear and unambiguous in support of, the view that
there is no implied limitation on the amending power. In Principle also it
aPPears unreasonable to suggest that the Constitution-makers wanted to provide
that the fundamental rights guaranteed by the Constitution should never be
touched by way of, amendment. In modern democratic thought I there are two main
trends-the liberal idea of individual 'rights (1) [1964] 1 S.C.R. 371 p 405.
(2) [1960] 3 S.C.R. 250.
935 protecting the individual and the
democratic idea proper pro claiming the equality of rights and popular
sovereignty .
The gradual extension of the idea of equality
from political to economic and social fields in the modern State has led to the
problems of social security, economic planning and industrial welfare
legislation. The implementation and harmonisation of these. somewhat
conflicting principles is a dynamic task. The adjustment between freedom and
compulsion, between the rights of individuals and the social interest and
welfare must necessarily be a matter for changing needs and conditions. The
proper approach is therefore to look upon the fundamental rights of the
individual as conditioned by the social responsibility, by the necessities of
the Society, by the balancing of interests and not as pre-ordained and
untouchable private rights.
As pointed out forcefully by Laski:
"The struggle for freedom is largely
transferred from the plane of political to that of economic rights. Men become
less interested in the abstract fragment of political power an individual can
secure than in the use of massed pressure of the groups to which they belong to
secure an increasing share of the social Product. Individualism gives way
before socialism. The roots of liberty are held to be in the ownership and
control of the instruments of production by the state, the latter using its
power to distribute the results of its regulation with increasing approximation
to equality. So long, as there is inequality, it is argued, there cannot be
liberty.
The historic inevitability of this evolution
was seen a century ago by de tocqueville. It is interesting to compare his
insistence that the democratization of political power meant equality and that
its absence would be regarded by the masses as oppression with the argument of
Lord Action that liberty and equality are antitheses. To the latter liberty was
essentially an autocratic ideal;
democracy destroyed individuality, which was
the very pith of liberty, by seeking identity of conditions. The modem emphasis
is rather toward the principle that material equality is growing inescapable
and that the affirmation of personality must be effective upon an immaterial
plane. it is found that doing as one likes, subject only to the demands of
peace, is incompatible with either international or municipal necessities. We
pass from contract to relation as we have passed from status to contract. Men
are so involved in intricate networks of relations that the place for their 936
liberty is in a sphere where their behaviour does not impinge upon that
self-affirmation of others which is liberty." (Encyclopaedia of the Social
Sciences, Vol. IX, 445.).
It must :not be forgotten that the
fundamental right guaranteedby Art. 31, for. instance. is not absolute. It
should be not that cl. (4) of that Article, provides an exception to the
requirements of cl. (2). 'Clause (4) relates 'to Billsof a State Legislature
relating to public acquisition which were pending at the-commencement of fhe
Co'stitution.
If such a Bill has been passed and assented
to by the President, the Courts shall have no jurisdiction to question the
validity of such law on the of contravention of cl. (2), ie., on the ground
that it does notprovide for compensation or that it has been enacted without a
public purpose. Clause (6) of the, Article is another exception to cl. (2) and
provides for ouster of jurisdiction of the Courts. While cl. (4) relates to
Bills pending in the State Legislature at the encement of the Constitution, cl.
(6) relates to Bills enacted by the State within IS I months before
commencement of the Constitution i.e., Acts providing for public acquisition
which were enacted not earlier than July 26, 1948. If the President certifies'
'such an Act within 3 months from the commencement of the Constitution, the
Courts shall have no jurisdiction to invalidate that Act on the ground of
contravention of cl. (2) of that Article Similarly, the scheme of Art 19
indicates that the fundamental rights guaranted by sub-cls. (a) to (g) of cl,
(1) can be validly regulated in the light of the provisions contained in cls.
(2) to (6) of Art. 19. In other words, the scheme of Art.19 is two-fold; the
fundamental rights of the citizens are of paramount importance, but even the
said fundamental rights can be regulated to serve the interests of the general
public or other objects mentioned respectively in cls. (2) to (6) of Art. 19.
It is right to state that the purposes for which fundamental rights can be
regulated which are s specified in cls. (2) to (6), could not have been assumed
by the Constitution-makers to be static and incapable of expansion. It cannot
be assumed that the Constitution-makers intended to forge a political strait
jacket for generations to come. The Constitution makers , must have anticipated
that in dealing with, socioeconomic problems which the 1egislatures may have to
face from time to time, the concepts of public interest and other important
considerations which are the basis of cls.
(2) to (6), may change and may even expand.
As Holmes' J.
has said in Abrams v. United States (1) :
"the .,Constitution is an experiMent, as
all life isan experiment". It is therefore legitimate to assume that the
Constitution-makers (1) 250 U.S. 616, 630.
937 intended that Parliament should be
competent to make amendments in these rights so as to meet the challenge of the
problems which may arise in the course of socioeconomic progress and
development of the country. I find it therefore difficult to accept the
argument of the petitioners than the Constitution-makers contemplated that
fundamental rights enshrined in Part III were finally and immutably settled and
determined once and for all and these rights are beyond the ambit of any future
amendment. Today at a time when absolutes are discredited, it must riot be too
readily assumed that there are basic features of the Constitution which shackle
the amending power and which take precedence over the general welfare of the
nation and the need for agrarian and social reform.
In construing Art. 368 it is moreover
essential to remember the nature and subject-matter of that Article and to
interpret it subject ae materies. The power of amendment is in point of quality
an adjunct of sovereignty. It is in truth the exercise of the highest sovereign
:power in the State. If the amending power is an adjunct of sovereignty it does
not Admit of any limitations. This view is expressed by Dicey in "Law of
the Constitution", 10th Edn., at page 148 as follows "Hence the power
of amending the constitution has been placed, so to speak, outside the
constitution, and that the legal sovereignty of the United States resides in
the States' governments as forming one aggregate body represented by
three-fourths of the several States at any time. belonging to the Union."
A similar view is stated by Lord Bryce in" "The" American
Commonwealth", Vol. 1, ch. XXXII, page 366. Lester Bernhardt Or field
states as follows in his book he Amending of the Federal Constitution"
"In the last analysis, one is brought to the conclusion that sovereignty
in the United States, if it can be said to exist at all, is located in the
amending body. The amending body has often beep referred to as the sovereign,
because it meets the fest of the location of sovereignty. As Willoughby has
said:
'In all those cases in which, owing to the
distribution of governing power, there is doubt as to the political body in
which the Sovereignty rests, the test to be applied is the determination of
which authority has, in the last instance, the legal power to determine its own
competence as well as that of others'.
938 Applying the criteria of sovereignty
which were laid down at the beginning of this chapter, the amending, body is
sovereign as a matter of both law and fact. Article Five expressly creates the
amending body. Yet in a certain manner of speaking the amending body may be
said to exist as a matter of fact since it could proceed to alter Article Five
or any other part of the Constitution. While it is true that the sovereign
cannot act otherwise than in compliance with law, it is equally true that it
creates the law in accordance with which it is to act." In his book
"Constitutional Law of the United States", Hugh Evander Willis says
that the doctrine of amendability of the Constitution is based on the doctrine
of the sovereignty of the people ,and that-it has no such implied limitations
as that an amendment shall not contain a new grant of , power nor be in the
form of legislation, nor change "our dual form of government nor change
the protection of the Bill of Rights, nor make any other change in the
Constitution." James G. Randall also enunciates the proposition that when
a constitutional amendment is adopted "it is done not by the 'general
government, but by the supreme sovereign power of the nation i.e., the people, acting
through State Legislatures or State conventions" and that "the
amending power is 'equivalent to the Constitution-make in power and is wholly
above 'the authority of the Federal Government"('Constitutional Pro Under
Lincoln', p. 395). , The legal position is summarised 'by Burdick at page 48 of
his treaties "The Law of the American Constitution as follows :
"The result of the National Prohibition
Cases (253 U.S. 350) seems to be that there is no limit to the power to amend
the Constitution, except that a State may not without its consent be deprived
of its equal suffrage in the Senate. To out the case most extremely, this means
that by action of two-third, of both Houses of Congress and of the,
legislatures in three-fourths , of the states all of the powers of the national
government could be surrendered to the States, or all of the reserved powers of
the States could be transferred to the federal government. It is only public
opinion acting upon these agencies which places any check upon the amending
power. But the alternative to this result would be to recognizethe power of the
Supreme Court to veto the will of the people expressed in a constitutional
amendment without any possibility of the reversal of the court's action except
through revolution." 939 The matter has been clearly put by George Vedel
in Manuel Elementaire De Droit Constitutionnel (Recueil Sirey) at page 117 as
follows :
"Truly speaking no constitution
prohibits for ever its amendment or its amendment in all its aspects.
But it can prohibit for example, the
amendment (revision) during a certain time (the Constitution of 1791) or it can
prohibit the amendment (revision) on this or that point (as in the Constitution
of 1875) which prohibits amendment of the republican form of Government and the
present Constitution follows the same rule.
But this prohibition has only a political but
no juridical value. In truth from the juridical viewpoint a declaration of
absolute , constitutional immutability cannot be imagined. The Constituent power
being the supreme power in the state cannot be fettered, even by itself. For
example,article 95 of our constitution stipulates, "The republican form of
Government cannot be the subject of a proposal for amendment.
But juridically the obstacle which this
provision puts in the way of an amendment of the republican form of government
can be lifted as follows.
It is enough to abrogate, by way of amendment
(revision) the article 95 cited, above. After this, the obstacle being removed,
a second amendment can deal with the republican form of Government.
In practice, this corresponds to the idea
that the constituent assembly of today cannot bind the nation of
tomorrow." the argument of implied limitation was advanced by Mr. N. C.
Chatterji and it was contended that item No.
3 of the IndoPakistan Agreement providing for a division of Berubari Union
between India and Pakistan was outside the power of constitutional amendment
and that the preamble to the, Constitution did not permit the dismemberment of
India but preserved the integrity of the territory of India. The argument was
rejected by this Court and it was held that Parliament acting under Art. 368
can make a law to give effect to and implement the Agreement in question or to
pass a law amending Art. 3 so as to cover cases of cession of the territory of
India and thereafter make a law under the amended Art. 3 to implement the
Agreement.
(1) [1960] 3 S.C.R. 250.
940 There is also another aspect of the
matter to be taken into account. If the fundamental rights are unamendable and
if Art. 368 does not include any such power it follows that the amendment of,
say, Art. 31 by insertion of Arts. 31-A and 31-B can only be made by a violent
revolution. It was suggested for the petitioners that an alteration of fundamental
rights could be made by convening a-new Constituent Assembly outside the
frame-work of the present Constitution, but it is doubtful if the proceeding,.,
of the new Constituent Assembly will have, 'any legal validity, for the reason
is that if the Constitution provides its own method of amendment, any other
method of amendment of the Constitution will be unconstitutional and void. For
instance, in George S. Hawke v. Harvey C. Smith, as Secretairy of State of
Ohio(1) it was held by the Supreme Court of the U.S.A. that Referendum
provisions. of State Constitutions' and statutes cannot be applied in the
'ratification or rejection of amendments to the Federal Constitution without
violating the requirements of Article 5 of such Constitution and that such
ratification shall be by the legislatures of the-several states, or by
conventions therein, as Congress shall decide. It was held in that case that
the injunction was properly issued against the calling of a referendum election
on the act of the legislature of a State ratifying an amendment to the Federal
Constitution.
If, therefore, the petitioners are right in
their contention that Art. 31 is not amendable within the frame-work of the
present Constitution, the only other recourse for making the amendment would,
as I have already said, be by revolution and not through, peaceful means, It
cannot be reasonably supposed. that the Constitution-makers contemplated that
Art. 31 or any other article on fundamental rights should be altered by
a-violent revolution and not by peaceful change.
It was observed in Feigenspan v. Bodine (2)
"If the plaintiff is right in its contention of lack of power to insert
the Eighteenth Amendment into the United States Constitution because of its
subject matter. it follows that there is no way to incorporate it and others of
like character into the national organic law, except, through revolution. This,
the plaintiff concedes, is the inevitable conclusion of its contention. This is
so starting a proposition that the judicial mind may be pardoned for not
readily acceding to it, and for insisting that only the most convincing reasons
will justify 'its acceptance." I am, therefore, of the opinion that the
petitioners Are unable to make good their argument on this aspect of: the case.
It was then contended for the
petitioners,that there would be anomalies if Art. 368 is interpreted to have no
implied limita(1) 64 L. Ed. 871. (2)264 Fed. 186.
941 tions. It was said that the more
important articles of the Constitution can be amended by the procedure
mentioned in the substantive part of Art. 368 but the less important articles
would require ratification by the legislatures of not less than half of the
States under the proviso to that Article. It was argued that the fundamental
rights and also Art. 32 could be amended by the majority of two-thirds of the
members of Parliament but Art. 226 cannot be amended unless there was
ratification of the legislatures of not less than halfof the States, It was
pointed out that Arts.
54 and 55 were more difficult to amend but
not Art. 52.
Similarly, Art.' 162 required ratification of
the States but not Art. 163 which related to the 'Council of Ministers to aid
and advise the Governor in the exercise of his functions. In my opinion the
argument proceeds on a misconception. The scheme of Art. 368 is not to divide
the Articles of the Constitution into two categories, viz., important and not
so important Article. It was contemplated by the Constitution-makers that the
amending power in the main part of Art. 368 should extend to each and every
article of the Constitution but in the case of such articles which related to
the federal principles or the relation of the States with the Union, the
ratification of the legislatures of at least half the States should be obtained
for any amendment. It was also contended that if Art. 368 was construed without
any implied limitation the amending power under that Article could be used for
subverting the Constitution. Both Mr. Asoke, Sen and Mr. Palkiwala resorted to the
method of reduction ad absurdem 'MI pointing out the abuses that might occur if
there were no limitations on the power to amend. It was suggested that
Parliament may, by a constitutional amendment, abolish the parliamentary system
of government or repeal the chapter of fundamental rights or divide India into.
two States, or even reintroduce the rule of a monarch. It.. is inconceivable
that 'Parliament should utilise the amending power for bringing about any of
these contingencies. It is, however, not permissible, in the first place, to
assume that in a matter of constitutional amendment there will be abuse of
power and then utilise it as a test for finding out the scope of the amending
power. This Court has declared repeatedly that the possibility of abuse is not
to be used as a test of the existence or extent of a legal power [See for
example, State of West Bengal v. Union of India(1), at page 407]. In the second
place, the amending power is a power, of an altogether different kind from the
ordinary governmental power and if an abuse occurs,, it occurs at the hands of
Parliament and the State Legislatures representing an extraordinary majority of
the people, so that for all practical purposes it may be said to be the people,
or at least. the highest agent of the people, and one exercising sovereign
powers. It is therefore (1) [1964]1 S.C.R. 371.
942 anomalous to speak of 'abuse' of a power
of this description. In the last analysis, political machinery and artificial
limitations will not protect the people from themselves. The perpetuity of our
democratic institutions will depend not upon special mechanisms or devices, nor
even upon any particular legislation, but rather upon the character and
intelligence and the good conscience of our people themselves. As observed by
Frankfurter, 1. in American Federation of Labour v. American Sash & Door
Co.(1) "But a democracy need rely on the courts to save it from its own
unwisdom. If it is alert-and without alertness by the people there can be no
enduring democracy unwise or unfair legislation can readily be removed from the
statute books. It is by such vigilance over its representatives that democracy
proves itself" I pass on to consider the next objection of the petitioners
that the true purpose and object of the impugned Act was to legislate in
respect of land and that legislation 1n respect of land falls within the
jurisdiction of State legislatures under Entry 18 of List 11, and the argument
was. that since the State Legislatures alone can make laws in respect of land,
Parliament had no right to pass the impugned Act. The argument was based on the
assumption that the impugned Act purports to be, and in fact is, a piece of
land legislation.
It was urged. that the scheme of Arts. 245
and 246 of the Constitution 'clearly showS that Parliament has no right to make
a law in respect of land, and since the impugned Act is a legislative measure
in relation to land, it is in Valid.
In my opinion, the argument is based upon a
misconception.
Whet the impugned Act purports to do is not
to make any land legislation but to protect and validate the legislative
measures in respect of agrarian reforms passed by the different State
Legislatures in the country by granting them immunity from attack based on the
plea that they contravene fundamental rights. The impugned Act was passed by
Parliament in exercise of the amending power conferred by Art. 368 and it is
impossible to accept the argument that the constitutional power of amendment
can be fettered by Arts. 245 and 246 or by the legislative Lists. It was argued
for, the petitioners that Parliament cannot validate a law Which it has no
Power to enact. The proposition holds good where the validity on impugned Act
turns on whether the subject-matter falls within or without the jurisdiction of
the legislature which passed it. But to make a law which contravenes the
Constitution constitutionally valid is a matter of constitutional amendment,
and as such it falls within the exclusive power of Parliament and within the
amending power conferred by Art. 368. I am accordingly of the opinion that the
petitioners are unable to (1) 335 U.S. 538,556.
943 substantiate their argument on this
aspect of the case. I should like to add that in Lesser v. Garnett(1), in
National Prohibition Cases(2 ) and in United States v. Sprague(3), a similar
argument Was advanced to the effect that a constitutional amendment was not
valid if it was in the form of legislation. But the argument was rejected by
the Supreme Court of the U.S.A. in all the three cases.
It remains to deal with the objection of the
petitioners that the newly inserted articles 31-A and 31-B require ratification
of the State legislatures under the proviso to Art. 368 of the Constitution
because these articles deprive the High Courts of the power to issue
appropriate writs under Art. 226 of the Constitution. I do not "think
there is any substance in this argument. The impugned Act does not purport to
change the provisions of Art. 226 and it cannot be, said even to have that
effect directly or in any substantial measure. It is manifest that the newly
inserted articles do I not either in terms or in effect seek to make any change
in Art. 226 of the Constitution. Article 31-A aims 'at saving laws providing
for the compulsory acquisition by the State of a certain kind-of property from
the operation of article 1 3 read with other relevant articles in Part III,
while article 31-b purports to validate certain specified Acts g Regulations,
already passed, which, but for such a; provision , would be liable to be
impugned under Art. 13 It is therefore' not correct to say that the powers of
High Courts to issue writs is, in'any way, affected. The jurisdiaction 'of the
High Courts remains just the same as it Was before. Only'a certain category-of
cases has been excluded from the purview of Part III and the High Courts can no
longer intervene, not because their Jurisdiction or powers have been curtailed
in any manner or to. any but because there would be no occasion hereafter for
the exercise of their power in such cases. As I have already said, the effect
of the impugned Act on the jurisdiction of the High Courts under Art. 226 of
the, Constitution is not direct but only incidental in character and therefore
the contention " of the petitioners on this point against the validity of
the impugned Act must be rejected.
It is well-settled that in examining a
constitutional question of this character, it is legitimate to consider whether
the impugned legislation is a legislation directly in respect of the
subject-matter covered by any particular article of the Constitution or whether
touches the said articles only incidentally or indirectly. In A. K. Gopalan v.
The State of Madras (4), kania , C.J., had occasion to consider the validity of
the argument that, the Preventive detention order resulted in the detention of
the applicant in a cell, and so, it contravened his fundamental rights
guaranteed by (1) 258 U. S. 130.
(2)253 U.S. 350.
(3) 282 U.S. 716.
(4) [1950] S.C.R 88101.
944 Art. 19(1)(a), (b), (c), (d), (e) and
(g)., Rejecting this argument, the learned Chief Justice observed that the true
approach in dealing with such a question was only to consider the directness of
the legislation and not what will be the result of the detention otherwise
valid, on the mode of the detenu's life. On that ground alone, he was inclined
to reject the contention that the order of detention contravened the
fundamental rights guaranteed to the petitioner under Art. 19(1). At page 100
of the report, Kania, C.J., stated as follows :
"As the preventive detention order
results in the detention of the applicant in a cell it was contended on his
behalf that the rights specified in Article 19(1) (a), (b), (c), (d), (e) and
(g) have been infringed. It was argued that because of his detention he cannot
have a free right to speech as and where he desired and the same argument was
urged in respect of the rest of the rights mentioned in sub-clauses (b), (c),
(d) (e) and (g).
Although this argument is advanced in a case
which deals with preventive detention, if correct, it should be applicable in
the case of punitive detention also to any one sentenced to a term of
imprisonment under the relevant section of the Indian Penal Code. So
considered, the argument must clearly be rejected. In spite of the saving
clauses (2) to (6), permitting abridgement of the rights connected with each of
them, punitive detention under several sections of the Penal Code, i.e., for
theft, cheating, forgery and even ordinary assault, will be illegaL Unless such
conclusion necessarily follows from the article, it is obvious that such
construction should be avoided. In my opinion, suc h result is. clearly not the
outcome of the Constitution. The article has to be read without any
pre-conceived notions. So read, it clearly means that the legislation to be
examined must be directly in respect of one of the rights mentioned in the
sub-clauses. If there is a legislation directly attempting to control a
citizen's freedom of speech or expression, or his right to assemble peaceably
and without arms, etc., the question whether that legislation is saved by the
relevant saving clause of article 19 will arise. If, however, the legislation
is not directly in respect of any of these subjects but as a, result of the
operation of other legislation, for instance, for punitive or preventive
detention, his right under any of these subclauses is abridged, the question of
the application of article 19 does not arise. 'Me true approach is only to
consider the directness of the legislation and not what will be the result of
the detention otherwise valid, on the mode of the detenu's 945 life. On that ,
short ground, in my opinion, this argument about the infringement of the rights
mentioned in article 19(1) generally must fail. Arty other construction put on
the article, it seems to me , will be unreasonIt is true that the opinion thus
expressed by Kania, C.J. in the case of A. K. Gopalan v. The State of Madras(-)
did not receive, the concurrence of the other learned Judges who heard the said
case. Subsequently, however, in Ram Singh & Others v. The State of Delhi
& Anr.(2) the said observations were cited with approval by the Full Court.
The same.
principle was accepted by this Court in
Express Newspapers (Pvt.) Ltd. v. The Union of India('), in the majority
judgment in Atiabari Tea Co. Ltd. v. The State of Assam (4 ) and in Naresh
Shridhar Mirajkar v. The State of Maharashtra("),. Applying the same
principle to the present case, consider that the effect of the impugned Act on
the powers of the High Court under Art. 226 is indirect and incidental and not
direct. I hold that the impugned Act falls under the substantive part of Art.
368 because the object of the impugned Act is to amend the relevant Articles in
Part III which confer fundamental rights on citizens and not -to change the
power of the High Courts under Art. 226.
In this connection I should like to refer to
another aspect of the matter. The question about the validity of the
Constitution (First Amendment) Act has been considered by, this Court in Sri
Sankari Prasad Singh Deo v. Union of India and State of Bihar(6). In that case,
the validity of the said Amendment Act was challenged, firstly, on the ground
that the newly inserted Arts. 31 -A and 31-B sought to make changes in Arts. 132
and 136 in Ch. IV of Part V and Art.
226 in Ch. V of Part VI. The second ground
was that the amendment was invalid because it related to legislation in respect
of land. It was also urged, in the third place, that though it may be open to
Parliament to amend the provisions in respect of fundamental rights contained
in Part ITT, the amendment made in that behalf would have to be tested in the
light of provisions of Art. 13(2) of the Constitution. The argument was that
the law to which Art.
13(2) applied would include a law passed by
Parliament by virtue of its constituent power to amend the Constitution, and
so, its validity will have to be tested by Art. 13(2) itself. All these
arguments were rejected by this Court and it was held in that case that the Constitution
(First Amendment) Act was legally valid. The same question arose for
consideration in Sajjan Singh v. State of Rajasthan (7) with regard to the
validity of the Constitution (Seventeenth Amendment) Act, 1964. In that case,
the petitioners in their (1) [1950 S.C.R. 88.
(2) [1951] S.C.R. 451,456.
(3) [1959] S.C.R. 12,129-30.
(4) [1961] 1 S.C.R. 809, 864.
(5) [1966] 3 S.C.R. 744. (6) [1995] 1 S.C.R.
89.
(7) [1963] 1 S.C. R. 933.
946 Writ Petitions in this Court contended
that the Constitution (Seventeenth Amendment)' Act was constitutionally invalid
since the powers Prescribed by Art. 226 which is in Ch. V, Part VI of the
Constitution Were likely to be affected by the Seventeenth Amendment, and
therefore the special procedure laid down under Art. 368 should have been
followed. It was further contended in that case that the decision of this court
in Sankari Prasads(1) case should be reconsidered. 'Both the contentions were
re-, rejected by this Court by' a majority Judgment and it was held that the
Constitution (Seventeenth Amendment) Act amended the fundamental rights solely
with the object of assisting the State Legislatures to give effect to the
socioeconomic policy of the party in power and its effect on Art. 226 was
incident and insignificant and the impugned Act therefore fell under the
substantive part of Art. 368 and did not attract the proviso to that article.
It was further held. by this Court that there Was no justification for reconsidering
Sankari Prasad's(1) case. On behalf of the respondents it was submitted by the
Additional Solicitor Generat that this was a very strong case for the
application of the principle of stare decisis. In my opinion, this contention
must be accepted as correct. If the arguments urged by the petitioners are to
prevail it would lead to the inevitable consequence that the amendments made to
the Constitution both in 1951 and in 1955 would be rendered invalid and. a
large number of decisions dealing with the validity of the Acts included in the
9th Schedule which were pronounced by this Court ever since, the decision in
Sankari Prasad's(1) case was declared, would also-have to be overruled. It was
also pointed out that Parliament, the Government and the people have acted on
the, faith of the decision of this Court in Sankari Prasad's(1) case and titles
to property have been transferred, obligations have been incurred and rights
have been acquird in the implementation of the legislation included in the 9th
Schedule.
The, effect of land reform legislation has been
clearly summarised in ch. VIII of Draft Outline on Fourth Plan as follows
"Fifteen years ago when the First Plan was being formulated, intermediary
tenures like zamindaris, jagirs and inams covered more than 40 per cent of the
area. There were large disparities in the ownership of land held under ryotwari
tenurer which covered the other 60 per cent area; and' a substantial portion of
the land was cultivated through tenants at will and share-croppers-who paid
about one half the produce as rent. Most holdings were small and fragmented.
Besides, there was a large population of landless agricultural labourers. In
these conditions, the, principal. measures recommended for securing the objectives
(1)[1952] S.C.R. 89.947 of the land policy were the abolition of intermediary
tenures, reform of the tenancy system, including fixation of fair rent at
one-fifth to one-fourth of the gross produce, security of I tenure for the
tenant, bringing tenants into direct relationship with the State and investing
in them ownership of land.
A ceiling on land holding was also recommended
so that some surplus land, may be made available for redistribution to the
landless agricultural workers. Another important part of, the progamme was
consolidation of agricultural holdings and in crese in the size of the
operational unit to an economic scale through cooperative methods.
Aboiition of Intermediaries.-During the past
15 years, progress has been made in several directions. Theprogramme for the
abolition of intermediaries has been carried out practically all over, the
country. About 20 million tenants of former intermediaries came into direct
relationship with the State and became owners of their holdings. State
Governments are now engaged in the assessment and payment of compensation.
There were some initial delays but a considerable progress hag been made in
this direction in recent years and it is hoped that the issue of compensatory
bonds will be completed in another two years.
Tenancy Reform.-TO deal with the problem of
tenants-at-will in the ryotwari areas and of 'sub'-tenants in the zamindari
areas, a good deal of legislation has been enacted. .
Provisions for security of tenure, for
bringing them into direct relation with the State and converting them into
owners have' been made in several States. As a result, about 3 million tenants
and sharecroppers have acquired ownership of 'More than 7 million acres.
Ceiling on Holdings. Laws imposing ceiling on
agricultural holdings have been enacted in all the States In the former Punjab
area, however the State Government has the power to settle tenants on land in
excess of the permissible limit although it has not set a ceiling on ownership.
According to available reports over 2 million acres of surplus areas in excess
of the ceiling limits have, been declared or taken possession of by
Government." It is true that the principle of stare decisis may not
strictly apply to, a decision on a constitutional point.
There is no restriction in the Constitution
itself which prevents this Court from reviewing its earlier decisions or even
to depart from them in the interest of public good. It is true that the problem
of construing constitutional provisions cannot be adequately solved by merely
adopting 948 the literal construction of the words used in, the various
articles. The Constitution is an organic document and it is intended to serve
as a guide to the solution of changing problems which the Court' may have to
face from time to time. It is manifest that in a progressive and dynamic society
the character of these problems is bound to change with the inevitable
consequence that the relevant words used in the Constitution may also change
their meaning and significance. Even so., the Court is reluctant to accede to,
the suggestion that its earlier decisions should be frequently reviewed or
departed from. In such a case the test should be : what is the nature of the
error alleged in the earlier decision, what is its impact on the public good
and what is the compelling character of the considerations urged in support of
the contrary view. It is also a relevant factor that the earlier decision has
been followed in, a large number of cases, that titles to property have passed
and multitude of rights and obligations have been created in consequence of the
earlier decision. I have already dealt with the merits of the contention of the
petitioners with regard to the validity of the impugned Act and I have given
reasons for holding that the impugned Act is constitutionally valid and the
contentions ,of the petitioners are unsound. Even on the assumption that it is
possible to take a different view and to hold that the impugned Act is
unconstitutional I am of opinion that the principle of state decisis must be
applied to the present case and the plea made by the, petitioners for
reconsideration of Sankari Prasad(1) case and the decision in Sajjan Singh v.
State of Rajasohan(2) is wholly unjustified and must be rejected.
In Writ Petition No. 202 of 1966, it was
contended by Mr. Nambyar that the continuance of the Proclamation of Emergency
under Art. 352 of the Constitution was a gross violation of power because the
emergency had ceased to exist. It was also contended that Art. 358 should be so
construed as to confine its operation on to legislative or executive action
relevant to the Proclamation of Emergency.
It was submitted that the Mysore State was
rot a border area and the land reform legislation of that State had no
relevant-connection with the Proclamation of Emergency and the fundamental
rights conferred by Art. 19 cannot be suspended so far as the petitions are
concerned. I do not think that it is necessary to express any opinion on these
points because the Writ Petition must fail on the other grounds which I have
already discussed above. It is also not necessary for me to express an opinion
on the doctrine of prospective overruling of legislation.
For the reasons already expressed I hold that
all these petitions fail and should be dismissed, but there will be no order as
to Petitions dismissed.
Costs.
G.C.
(1) [1952] S.C.R. 89.
(2) [1965] S.C.R. 933.
Back